Flora Unveiled

(backadmin) #1
Idealism and Asexualism j 437

437 437


On the other hand, Kant scoffed at the idea that Bildungstrieb could ever be explained by
mechanical principles:

It is quite certain that we cannot become sufficiently acquainted with organized crea-
tures and their hidden potentialities by aid of purely mechanical natural principles,
much less can we explain them; and this is so certain, that we very boldly assert that it
is absurd for man even to conceive such an idea, and to hope that a Newton may one
day arise even to make the production of a blade of grass comprehensible, according
to natural laws ordained by no intentions, such an insight we must absolutely deny
to man.^22

Although Kant was adamant that scientists would never comprehend the nature of
Bildungstrieb, he believed that they could at least chip away at the problem by studying
those aspects of Bildungstrieb that fell within the categories of understanding.^23 For Kant,
the utility of the term Bildungstrieb lay mainly in its heuristic value. It permitted biologists
to proceed with their investigations of mysterious phenomena as if the organism were acting
purposively, guided by some unseen intelligence.
During the Enlightenment, the psychological gulf between artists and scientists had
grown wider. Humanists felt the pain of this schism more acutely than scientists did, and
one of the chief goals of the Romantic movement was to bring about a reunification of aes-
thetics and the natural sciences. In Critique of Judgement, Kant attempted to provide the
philosophical foundation for such a reunification by comparing the “purposive character of
beautiful objects and organic nature.”^24 The primary “purpose” of art was to be beautiful.^25
But the creation of a beautiful art object could not be reduced to a set of instructions; oth-
erwise, anyone could be an artist. How, then, does the artist know how to create beautiful
objects? And how does the observer gazing at a work of art recognize it as beautiful?
According to Kant, the act of perceiving a work of art sets the imagination free to reso-
nate with the harmony of the artwork, thus evoking a feeling of pleasure. If the feeling
exceeds a certain threshold, the object is judged to be beautiful. In general, artists, com-
posers, and poets are people who have an intuitive grasp of the forms and patterns that
create harmonious feelings in others, a deep- seated awareness of what Richards calls the
“subjectively- felt laws of harmony.”^26 “Genius,” according to Kant, “is the talent that gives
the rule to art.” The art critic may attempt to identify elements that make a work of art
beautiful, but ultimately the attempt fails because beauty is an ineffable quality grounded
in consciousness.
Living organisms, like works of art, exhibit beautiful forms and patterns produced
by harmoniously interacting elements, which, while ineffable, seem to be created by the
Bildungstrieb, or formative power. The only way biologists can study living organisms, says
Kant, is teleologically— that is, as though they had been created according to a blueprint or
“archetype,” just as the Renaissance sculptor, Michelangelo, is reputed to have said that his
job was to liberate the forms imprisoned in marble:

In every block of marble I see a statue as plain as though it stood before me, shaped and
perfect in attitude and action. I have only to hew away the rough walls that imprison
the lovely apparition to reveal it to the other eyes as mine see it.^27
Free download pdf