Krohs_00_Pr.indd

(Jacob Rumans) #1

34 Mark Perlman



  1. In a different fi eld, that of mental content, I see the same kind of problem. Fodor’s (1987) notion of “asym-
    metric dependence” as a theory of content may well get all the cases right, and skirt the counterexamples, but
    it just seems too convoluted to be a basic rule of nature, that is, too arcane and messy to be what content or
    meaning is.

  2. See also Fodor (1990), Neander (1995, 1996), and Enç (2002).


References


Allen, C., and Bekoff, M. (1995). Function, natural design, and animal behavior: Philosophical and ethological
considerations. Perspectives in Ethology, 11: 1–47.
Alston, W. (1989). Epistemic Justifi cation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Ariew, A. (2002). Platonic and Aristotelian roots. In: Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology
and Biology (Ariew, A., Cummins, R., Perlman, M., eds.), 7–32. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press.
Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Audi, R. (1988). Belief, Justifi cation, and Knowledge. Belmont, Calif.: Wadsworth Publishing Company.
Beckner, M. (1959). The Biological Way of Thought. New York: Columbia University Press.
Bedau, M. A. (1990). Against mentalism in teleology. American Philosophical Quarterly, 27: 61–70.
Bedau, M. A. (1991). Can biological teleology be naturalized? The Journal of Philosophy, 88: 647–655.
Bedau, M. A. (1992a). Goal-directed systems and the good. The Monist, 75: 34–49.
Bedau, M. A. (1992b). Where’s the good in teleology? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52:
781–806.
Bedau, M. A. (1993). Naturalism and teleology. In: Naturalism: A Critical Appraisal (Wagner, S., and Warner,
R., eds.), 23–51. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press.
Bigelow, J., and Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. The Journal of Philosophy, 84: 181–196.
BonJour, L. (1985). The Structure of Empirical Knowledge. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Boorse, C. (1976). Wright on functions. Philosophical Review, 85: 70–86.
Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44: 542–573.
Boorse, C. (2002). A rebuttal on functions. In: Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and
Biology (Ariew, A., Cummins, R., Perlman, M., eds.), 63–112. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press.
Buller, D. (1998). Etiological theories of function: A geographical survey. Biology and Philosophy, 13:
505–527.
Cameron, R. (2003). How to be a realist about sui generis teleology—yet feel at home in the 21st century. The
Monist, 87: 72–95.
Canfi eld, J. (1966). Introduction. In: Purpose in Nature (Canfi eld, J., ed.), 1–7. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall.
Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. The Journal of Philosophy, 72: 741–765.
Cummins, R. (2002). Neo-teleology. In: Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and
Biology (Ariew, A., Cummins, R., Perlman, M., eds.), 157–172. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press.
Dipert, R. R. (1993). Artifacts, Art Works, and Agency. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Dretske, F. I. (1986). Misrepresentation. In: Belief: Form, Content and Function (Bogdan, R. J., ed.), 17–36.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Enç, B. (2002). Indeterminacy of function attributions. In: Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychol-
ogy and Biology (Ariew, A., Cummins, R., Perlman, M., eds.), 291–313. Oxford and New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press.

Free download pdf