321435_Print.indd

(やまだぃちぅ) #1
state—a personal feel of redness for example. The zombie example claims that
we can imagine people who have no phenomenal states at all but have bodies
and brains just like everyone else. Dualists claim that because zombies are
imaginable, but very different from ordinary people, the imaginability of zom-
bies proves that ordinary people are something in addition to their physical
properties. Naturally, physicalists disagree. They claim that the mere fact that
we canimaginea zombie does not mean that they arepossiblein the sense
required to prove that phenomenal experiences require non-physical properties.
Imaginability does not prove possibility.

The arguments continue with no likelihood of quick resolution. The thought


experiments are intended to show that subjective experience cannot be explained by


neurology alone or for that matter by any other purely physical process.


Philosophers of mind vary in their opinions about what they prove. Small wonder


that human biologists who venture into similar areasfind puzzles of their own.


There is some agreement among philosophers regarding phenomenal experience


or what we commonly call mental experiences. One distinctive feature is that such


experiences areepistemically privileged.We have special kinds of knowledge about


the phenomena, and such knowledge comes with an especially high degree of


certainty. I know with certainty that a certain patchlooks red, even though I may be


mistaken about what in the objective world caused me to perceive the patch.
A related point is that no one else in the world can have evidence that can rea-


sonably cause me to doubt my own honest beliefs about the phenomenal appear-


ance of the patch. A very clever neurologist might be able to infer that I am seeing a


reddish patch by watching my fMRI output, but if we disagree, the neurologist (and


not me) must be mistaken. My epistemic privilege trumps the neurologist’s


objectively based opinion, no matter how long his educational career or how short


mine. (To simplify the discussion, I will sidestep an interesting anthropological


complication, by assuming that the neurologist and I share our culture. Many


anthropologists are aware that different languages have different numbers of color


words and somewhat different ways of dividing up the color spectrum. The pos-


sibility that this shows that people from different cultures actually perceive colors


differently will be ignored for the moment.)


This excursion into deepest philosophy raises the following questions: Are the


biological and health correlates of the biomarkers discussed in this volumesub-


jectivein a sense similar to the subjectivity of phenomenal experience? Can a


philosophical distinction be drawn between (objective) biomarkers and the (sub-


jective) experiences that they mark, paralleling the distinction between my objective


brain states and my subjective phenomenal experiences? The objective–subjective


dichotomy does touch on a few of the biomarkers here discussed, but not all of


them. Some biological correlates are themselves purely objective, equally objective


as their biomarkers. Blood test results may be an example, e.g., cholesterol levels.


But the biomarkers all mark factsabout us, and some of those are facts about which


we consider ourselves to beprivileged knowers. If we are privileged knowers about
our health conditions, our privilege might challenge the legitimacy of the


14 Subjective and Objective Knowledge: Persistent Puzzles 305

Free download pdf