321435_Print.indd

(やまだぃちぅ) #1

of sweating, etc.) nicely correlate with subjective reports of hotflashes that happen


in the laboratory during waking hours, and subjects often awaken when biomarkers


indicate that such an episode is occurring. But sometimes the biomarkers occurred


but the subject does not awaken. Did this subject have a hotflash (as the objective


measures stated) or not (as she reported)? This quasi-conflict is minor, but it does


exist. Did an apparent itch that you scratched while asleep really exist (as an itch) or


not? The ontology of itches is a minor topic, even among philosophers, but the


contradiction exists.


Rudzik and Ball (Chap. 3 , this volume) discuss a problem similar in its sub-


jective–objective structure to that of Fisher and Thurston. They examine the phe-


nomenon of baby-lag or parental exhaustion due to sleep loss. Their emic


documentation reveals how dramatic the phenomenon can be. But there are still


puzzles of subjective–objective mismatch. Is a parent who actually has little or no


objectively measured sleep loss butfeelsexhausted a subject of baby-lag? Must we


find causes other than literal sleep loss, for subjective exhaustion? Conversely, is a


parent who loses sleep but does not report exhaustionnota subject for the study?


One is reluctant simply to allow the subject’s own self-diagnosis to rule the


investigation, but such problems call for some remediation.


More complex problems occur with regard to Weber and Maki’s report


(Chap. 13 , this volume) of subjective memory complaints (SMC). The authors
examine whether SMC correlate with objectively measurable memory problems.


They report that a major study reassured its study population that memory worries


are‘generally unfounded.’This conclusion stemmed largely from the fact that SMC


are extremely widespread. It is certainly true that the significance of a potential


medical problem is diminished when thousands of people falsely come to believe


that the problem applies to them. This is a frequent effect of media coverage. But


the authors also report that subsets of people who make SMC actually do have


testable memory problems, for example, among some women experiencing


menopause. So, although we would not want to regard SMC as epistemically


privileged, neither would we want to dismiss such complaints. A widespread dif-


ficulty is the fact that many different abilities are involved with what lay people


label simply‘memory’(speed of recall, attention, concentration, etc.). If the lack of


correspondence between SMC and objective confirmation arises simply from the


smaller set of labels used by subjects, perhaps this is merely a matter of commu-


nication between the healthcare professional and patient.


By far the most interesting study for the subjective–objective puzzles is Brown’s


study (Chap. 7 , this volume). Brown’s data lead him to ask the question that came


up in the previous paragraphs: when a biomarker exists without subjective con-


sciousness of the state that it is presumed to mark, what do we say about it? That the


state existed unperceived, or that the state had not existed? Brown discusses a


number of experimental results that raise these puzzles, and he proposes ways of


avoiding the paradoxes. One experiment compared the emic reports and biomarkers


of two linguistically (and presumably culturally) distinct groups of Filipino


immigrants in Hawaii. One of the groups reported a significantly higher level of
stress than the other. However, the stress-related biomarkers for the groups were not


14 Subjective and Objective Knowledge: Persistent Puzzles 307

Free download pdf