Phylogenetic Species Concepts 247
Like Hennig and most proponents of the biospecies and other isolationist concep-
tions, they reject the use of a single taxonomic category such as species to apply to
asexual (“uniparental”) organisms. Instead, they call them “agamotaxa.”
A set-theoretic model of Hennig’s concept has been provided by Kornet (under
the title of “internodal species concept”) who formalizes the notion of internodal-
ity (INT) in a cladogram in terms of the tokogenetic relations being permanently
divided, so that any individual in the hologenetic group has a “gross dynastic rela-
tionship” (GDYN) with any other individual in that group.^28 Type specimens thus
fall out as an appropriate individual to start the GDYN analysis to establish the INT
relation. Kornet thus makes the relation of type specimens to the rest of the species
scrutable (see below) in set theoretic terms.
The Hennig account is fundamentally a biospecies concept. Hennig himself
accepted that species were reproductively isolated, and the criteria used for iden-
tifying the relevant phylogenetic edges of the cladogram are simply those of the
biospecies. We could therefore say that it is better considered to be considered under
that rubric, and that the issue of “extinction” of species at cladogenesis is one of the
reference of taxonomic names. In short, the “extinction” is a taxonomic extinction.^29
Phylogenetic Taxon (Synapomorphic) Species
There are many other conceptions that their authors refer to, or which are referred
to by others, as “phylogenetic” conceptions of species. It is not clear that these form
a natural class of conceptions. I believe there are two basic approaches that derive
from the cladistic terminology, but it is not therefore the case that all authors in
one or the other classes agree or that cladistic terminology resolves the differences
between them.
Synapomorphy-based species are largely due to the advocacy of Brent Mishler,
although earlier Joel Cracraft had defined the species taxon as
... the smallest diagnosable cluster of individual organisms within which there is a
parental pattern of ancestry and descent.^30
Mishler and Brandon summarize their Monophyletic version:
A species is the least inclusive taxon recognized in a classification, into which organ-
isms are grouped because of evidence of monophyly (usually, but not restricted to,
the presence of synapomorphies), that is ranked as a species because it is the smallest
‘important’ lineage deemed worthy of formal recognition, where ‘important’ refers to
the action of those processes that are dominant in producing and maintaining lineages
in a particular case.^31
(^28) Kornet 1993, Kornet and McAllister 1993.
(^29) In the context of the debate between Mayr and Hennig over the “correct” way to classify [Mayr 1974,
Hennig 1975], Hennig criticizes Mayr for ambiguity in his terms, which lends support to this inter-
pretation. Above all, Hennig wanted clarity.
(^30) Cracraft 1983, 170.
(^31) Mishler and Brandon 1987, also in Hull and Ruse 1998, 310. See also Mishler and Donoghue 1982.