256 Species
Some part of the resource space together with whatever predation and parasitism
occurs on the group considered.^5
Quercus species are often sympatric, and freely hybridize, and yet they maintain
their identity. He refers to these groups as “multispecies,” as they exchange genes,
but he does not require that they actually form viable hybrids that breed true there-
after. “Multispecies” is defined as a
... set of broadly sympatric species that exchange genes in nature ...^6
and refers to the syngameon concept of Verne Grant, which, we have seen, is due to
Poulton. Multispecies can occur without having component species as such, citing
Rubus, Crataegus, and dandelions. The latter leads to the implication that asexuals
are not to be considered species.
Elsewhere Littlejohn has comprehensively reviewed reproductive isolation, and
he makes some interesting comparisons between sexual reproduction and asexual
isolation.^7 He notes that asexuals (uniparental species; unlike many of his predeces-
sors, Littlejohn does not exclude them from specieshood) must be seen as a “clus-
ter or cloud of individuals representing an adaptive node or adaptive peak,” and
cites Dobzhansky and G. E. Hutchinson. Hutchinson employs a “taxonomic space”
model, and treats species as clusters in that space, formed through adaptation.^8 This
is somewhat different to the phenetic concept of an operational taxonomic unit
(OTU). For a start, he requires independence of the axes of the space, and that they
be adaptive characters. Asexuals, such as bdelloid rotifers, are just as good species
as their close sexual relatives, the Nebalia class of crustaceans.^9 Similar points about
the role of adaptation in delimiting species were previously made by entomologist
R. S. Bigelow, who noted that
Reproductive isolation [in Mayr’s 1963 definition—JSW] should be considered in
terms of gene flow, and not in terms of interbreeding, since selection will inhibit gene
flow between well-integrated gene pools despite interbreeding.^10
Recently, the philosopher Kim Sterelny defended an “ecological mosaic” con-
ception of species,^11 based on a reworking of Dobzhansky’s metaphor of species
as occupying “adaptive peaks” in a Wrightean fitness landscape.^12 Noting that spe-
cies are typically ecologically fractured,^13 Sterelny concludes that most species are
geological and ecological mosaics, and are not ecologically cohesive entities. He
takes this to explain stasis in the duration of species, because interbreeding between
(^5) Op. cit., 234.
(^6) Op. cit., 235.
(^7) Littlejohn 1981.
(^8) Hutchinson 1968.
(^9) I am indebted to Dr. Littlejohn for providing me with these references.
(^10) Bigelow 1965, 458.
(^11) Sterelny 1999.
(^12) Dobzhansky 1937, 9–10.
(^13) Sterelny 1999, 124.