Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon tWo: tHe BRAIn
    in the microtubules). If quantum computing does occur in the brain, this is very
    important, but it only adds another layer of complexity to the way the brain
    works. If there is a hard problem, it might be rephrased here as ‘How does subjec-
    tive experience arise from objective reduction in the microtubules?’ The strange
    effects entailed in quantum processes do not, of themselves, have anything to
    say about the experience of light or space or pain or the colour of the traffic light.
    They do not explain why there is experience rather than no experience. American
    philosopher Jesse Prinz refers to ‘those pesky quantum phenomena that are a
    refuge for non-mysterians with an appetite for the mysterious’ (2003, p. 116). Koch
    and Hepp (2006/2007; here in preprint [2007], p. 1) call the connection between
    quantum mechanics and consciousness an ‘entertaining topic at parties’ but
    argue that evidence from biophysics and computational neuroscience makes any
    connection unlikely. Samanta Pino and Ernesto Di Mauro (peer commentary on
    Hameroff and Penrose, 2014, here p. 92) wonder whether the lack of alternative
    explanations may be making quantum physics seem more promising than it
    should for tackling the ‘intricately unapproachable’ unknown that is conscious-
    ness. And Pat Churchland concludes that ‘Pixie dust in the synapses is about as
    explanatorily powerful as quantum coherence in the microtubules’ (1998, p. 121).
    But the theory may at least have the benefit of pushing us closer towards a need
    for ‘falsifiable verification’, Pino and Di Mauro concede (p. 92); and Hameroff and
    Penrose respond confidently that the proposed form of objective reduction ‘may
    be fairly close to either experimental confirmation or refutation’ (p. 99). So, quan-
    tum processing may yet turn out to be the solution to the hard problem, but so far
    it seems mainly to have moved the problem into a microtubule-shaped theatre.


MULTIPLE DRAFTS
The most concerted attempt to ditch the theatre is probably Dennett’s multiple
drafts theory, which he proposed as an alternative to Cartesian materialism.
‘When you discard Cartesian dualism’, Dennett says,
you really must discard the show that would have gone on in the
Cartesian Theatre, and the audience as well, for neither the show nor the
audience is to be found in the brain, and the brain is the only real place
there is to look for them.
(1991, p. 134)

This wholesale rejection of the idea of ‘me’ can be deeply unsettling. So much
so that Dennett has even been called ‘the Devil’, his ideas needing ‘an exorcism,
aimed at eliminating the spectre of materialist reductionism from the science of
consciousness’ (Voorhees, 2000, p. 55).
In multiple drafts theory, perceptions, emotions, thoughts, and all kinds of cog-
nitive activity are accomplished in the brain by multitrack parallel processes that
interpret and elaborate sensory inputs, and all are under continuous revision.
Like the many drafts of a book or article, perceptions and thoughts are constantly
revised and altered, and at any point in time there are multiple drafts of narrative
fragments at various stages of editing in various places in the brain.

You may then want to ask, ‘but which ones are conscious?’ If you do so, you are
imagining a Cartesian theatre in which only some of these drafts are re-presented

‘Pixie dust in the


synapses is about as


explanatorily powerful


as quantum coherence


in the microtubules’


(Churchland, 1998, p. 121)


‘Daniel Dennett is the


Devil’


(Voorhees, 2000, pp. 55–56)

Free download pdf