Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon tWo: tHe BRAIn
    probably have noticed and then remembered the light changing to red, and been
    convinced that you were conscious of it. This is also why, when we ask, ‘am I  con-
    scious now?’, the answer is always yes; and why, when we ask, ‘what was I conscious
    of a moment ago?’, there seems to be an easy answer. But since there was no probe
    during your drive that led to speech or memory encoding (only those leading to
    changing gears and pressing pedals), you conclude  – if you should happen to
    reflect on the journey once you get to work – that you were unconscious of the red
    light at the time. The only difference is because of the probes that were applied,
    or not. If the probing is done using language, as it often is, the role of the ‘second
    person’ – of social action and interaction, especially through discourse – becomes
    important in ways we will explore more thoroughly in Chapter 17.
    We can compare this theory with the others in terms of our three crucial ques-
    tions: does it help with the problem of why we have subjective experience at all,
    does it try to explain the difference between conscious and unconscious events,
    and does it posit some kind of theatre? The answer to all three is an obvious, and
    defiant, ‘no’. There is no theatre, no difference between conscious and uncon-
    scious events or processes, and as for subjectivity, multiple drafts theory throws
    out most of the assumptions that we usually make about it.
    If we think that at any time there is a truth about what ‘I’ am sub-
    jectively experiencing now, then we are wrong. This is why Den-
    nett is able to say, ‘But what about the actual phenomenology?
    There is no such thing’ (1991, p. 365). And this in turn may be why
    critics complain that Dennett has not explained consciousness
    but explained it away. Yet, he claims that his theory does deal
    with subjectivity. He describes a rich experience of sitting in his
    rocking chair, watching the sunlight on the trees and listening to
    music. This description, he says, is just one of the many possible
    ways the parallel stream could have been probed. If we ask, ‘but
    what was he actually experiencing at the time?’, there is no right
    answer. If we sit now and ask, ‘what am I conscious of now?’, the
    answer will also depend on how the stream is probed. As inner
    speech is produced so content becomes fixed, and we conclude
    that ‘I’ was watching the white fluffy clouds go by. This is how the
    experience and the experiencer come to be created. This is what
    brains do. This, according to Dennett, is how experience can be
    electrochemical happenings in a brain.
    If you find multiple drafts difficult and worrying, then you are
    probably beginning to understand it. It is difficult to understand
    because doing so means throwing out many of our usual habits
    of thought concerning our own consciousness. If you want to
    give this theory a fair hearing before deciding on its merits, then
    you really need to try to understand it with an open mind, setting
    aside your natural assumptions. This is not easy to do, but does
    get easier with practice. The process may feel like identifying the
    routes your thoughts naturally travel down, and then gently, at
    a critical point, opening up a new path. And remember, if you
    decide, having given it a real try, that the theory doesn’t work,
    you can always go back to the old path.


‘there are no fixed


facts about the stream


of consciousness


independent of


particular probes’


(Dennett, 1991, p. 138)


ACtIVItY 5.1
Cartesian materialism

Almost no one admits to being a Cartesian materialist,
yet the literature about consciousness is full of
theatrical metaphors and phrases implying that things
are ‘in’ or ‘out’ of consciousness. It is worth trying to
sort out what these mean before making up your own
mind about the theatre of consciousness. If you are
doing this as a class exercise, ask each person to find
examples in advance and bring them for discussion.
Theories. For any theory of consciousness ask, ‘Does
this theory use theatre imagery or metaphors? If so,
is it a Cartesian theatre? Is this a form of Cartesian
materialism?’
Tell-tale phrases. Look out for theatre imagery,
or phrases that imply CM, in any area of psychology,
philosophy, or neuroscience. Here are a few examples.
In each case ask whether this imagery is helpful, or a
sign of problems with the theory.
‘There seems to be a presence-chamber in my mind
where full consciousness holds court’ (Galton, 1883,
p. 203)
‘ideas [.. .] pass in rapid succession through the mind’
(James, 1890, pp. 25–26)
Free download pdf