Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon FoUR: eVoLUtIon
    that their visual field is filled with uniformly detailed
    information’, or persuading them that they understand
    things they do not (Sloman and Chrisley, 2003, pp. 137–
    138). We might think we would be better off without
    pain, but in fact those few unfortunate individuals who
    cannot feel pain constantly damage themselves. Then
    there is that old chestnut, the redness of red – the ‘raw
    feel’, the quale. This we get completely wrong, says Brit-
    ish physiologist Horace Barlow. When we say ‘This apple
    is red’, we may, from introspection, think that the raw
    sensation of red comes first, when in fact much com-
    putation is required, and the way we experience red
    depends on our whole history of seeing red objects and
    talking about them. Barlow argues that ‘the sensation
    of redness is merely preparing you to communicate the
    fact that something is red; this is another case where introspection is misleading, for
    redness is a carefully cooked product and is never as raw as it seems’ (1987, p. 372).
    This is reminiscent of James’s claim that ‘No one ever had a simple sensation by itself ’
    (1890, i, p. 224). Barlow concludes that consciousness is a social product derived
    from communication and cannot be explained by introspection.
    Another objection is that Humphrey’s notion of consciousness is dualist, that the inner
    eye is a ghost in the machine or an audience of one in its Cartesian theatre, but he
    makes clear that this is not, in spite of the diagram, what he means. Rather, the inner
    eye is an aspect of the way the human brain functions. But how can a brain describe
    itself? Who is the observer inside the brain, and doesn’t this lead to an infinite regress
    of ever more observers? Humphrey says not. Consciousness, he says, is a feature not
    of the whole brain but only of the added self-reflexive loop whose output is part of
    its own input. No regress is implied, he claims. Yet he does admit there is a problem.
    ‘Why this particular arrangement should have what we might call the “transcendent”,
    “other-worldly” qualities of consciousness I do not know’ (2002, p. 75).
    Do Humphrey and Mithen really see consciousness as itself having a function that
    is acted on by natural selection (Type 2 in Concept 11.1), or do they try to explain
    why any creature capable of introspection or self-reflective insight must inevita-
    bly be conscious (Type 3)?
    The answer appears to be the former. Both Humphrey and Mithen describe con-
    sciousness as an emergent property with specific functions on which natural
    selection can act, such as ‘giving the subject a picture of his own brain activity’
    (Humphrey, 2002, p. 76).
    This may leave us with a fundamental doubt. Is consciousness really the kind of
    thing that can be a surface feature or an emergent property, like fur or wetness
    or intelligence? As ever, we must remember that consciousness means subjective
    experience, or ‘what it is like to be’. So the question for these theories is, does
    natural selection act on how it feels to introspect or on the behavioural conse-
    quences of introspection? If you decide the latter, then the subjective experience
    has no evolutionary function in its own right. Both its existence and the reason
    why it evolved remain unexplained.
    Interestingly, Humphrey’s later work tries to avoid this problem and so belongs in
    the next section.


EXPERIENCEINTROSPECTIVEMESSAGESURVIVALVALUE

Pain

Love

Redness

Unpleasantandtobe
avoided
Desire forlifelong
attachment,feelings of
unboundedadmiration,etc.
Attribute of a physicalobject

Minimises injuries

Propagationofthe
humanspecies

Abilityto
communicate about
this attribute

Introspectionon ourexperiences does notdirectlytellus theirsurvival
value

FIGURE 11.7 • According to Barlow, introspection
on our experiences does not
accurately reflect their survival
value (Barlow, 1987, p. 364).

Free download pdf