Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon FIVe: BoRDeRLAnDs
    A psychological and neurobiological review of ASCs (Vaitl
    et al., 2005) included states experienced spontaneously,
    stimulated by physical or psychological means, or caused
    by illness, resulting in a four-dimensional model. The dimen-
    sions are activation (low to high arousal), awareness span (a
    narrow to broad range of ‘contents available to attention and
    conscious processing’, p. 114), self-awareness (diminished to
    heightened), and sensory dynamics (reduced to heightened
    sensation). The authors present their four dimensions as a
    first step towards constructing what they call the ‘C-space’:
    the space of states of consciousness. The counterpart to
    the C-space is the ‘B-space’: the space of functional brain
    states. The challenge is to create mappings between the
    two, whether these are understood as strict one-to-one
    mappings or as one-to-many or many-to-many mappings. In
    any case, they argue that with state–space approaches we
    should only ever expect the locations in both spaces to be
    ‘blurred’ (determined with limited resolution), meaning the
    final mappings will always be coarse-grained and probabi-
    listic (p. 119).


This really is a big challenge  – to bring together subjective
experiences of altered states with what we know of the
underlying physiology. Some people have an enormously
wide range of experiences over their lifetimes. They may
have taken many different drugs, practised meditation,
yoga, or Tai Chi over long periods, and used TMS, sensory iso-
lation tanks, or other kinds of ‘phenotechnology’, as Thomas
Metzinger calls it. In these ways, they may have gained a
good personal understanding of how to shift from state to
state, how to maintain or leave a given state, and how
each state can be used, but as yet this kind of under-
standing has not been systematically integrated into
academic research.
We may imagine a future in which we thoroughly under-
stand the nature of phenospace and the various technol-
ogies that can move us around within it. Metzinger claims
that with this knowledge we should in principle be able to
design our own ego tunnels (conscious experiences which
we attribute to our selves) by tinkering with the hardware
that supports them.

Whether the desired phenomenal content is
religious awe, an ineffable sense of sacredness,
the taste of cinnamon, or a special kind of sexual
arousal does not really matter. So, what is your
favourite region of phenospace? What conscious
experience would you like to order up?
(2009, pp. 220–221)

PRoFILe 13.1
Thomas Metzinger (b. 1958)
Thomas Metzinger is no one. A German
philosopher, and director of research groups
in neuroethics and theoretical philosophy at
the Johannes Gutenberg University of Mainz,
he claims that no one ever had or was a self.
In Being No One, and his later book The Ego Tunnel, he
argues that what we take to be persistent entities are really
ongoing processes: the contents of transparent self models.
He has experienced and written about many ‘altered states’,
including lucid dreams, out-of-body experiences, medita-
tion, and drug-induced experiences, and is concerned about
the ethical implications of our rapidly advancing phenotech-
nology. When we can choose which areas of phenospace
we want to visit, or can enhance our cognitive skills with
specially tailored chemicals, we will need to take responsi-
bility for the consequences. Hence much of his work is in the
new field of neuroethics. Metzinger was a co-founder of the
Association for the Scientific Study of Consciousness and has
edited books on conscious experience and the NCCs.

FIGURE 13.6 • The chemical structures of some
well-known psychoactive drugs.
Many of these resemble the
structure of neurotransmitters.

Free download pdf