Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon sIx: seLF AnD otHeR
    Language is a crucial mediator of this emergence. The function of language is not
    to encode a set of neural representations; saying I am angry ‘is more like a hand-
    shake or an embrace than a mirror of the interior’ (Gergen, 2011, pp. 646–647).
    To say something is to perform an action within a relationship, and so ‘private
    feelings’ are better thought of as public actions: ‘it is not that one has emotions, a
    thought, or a memory so much as one does them’ (p. 647). And just as we cannot
    make ourselves understood if we use words we’ve just made up, so our actions
    do not make sense unless they draw on cultural traditions. Thus all our perfor-
    mances of self carry a history of relationships, and extend that history: ‘The other
    enters expressions of the self in their very formulation’ (p. 647). This is true even –
    or especially  – for prisoners held in solitary confinement, who survive only by
    creating social worlds for themselves and by knowing that there are others who
    remember them. In conditions like this, where the volume is turned down on the
    everyday, it becomes clearer than ever that ‘Others think of me therefore I exist’
    (Saunders, 2014, p. 93).
    If we follow this path consistently, ‘the other’ stops seeming to be outside, but
    becomes part of the self. Selves don’t first exist and then have intersubjectivity
    or sociality added to them: those qualities are just as intrinsic to them as embod-
    iment. These qualities also connect directly to embodiment, as is clear in various
    important developmental activities in human children, such as imitation (learn-
    ing by copying others’ physical movements) and joint attention (attending to
    something along with someone else, like a mother and daughter reading a book
    together). In ways like these, we act with others, attend to others, and attend with
    others, and this way our shared experiences are part of who we are. And so the
    self is fundamentally ‘dialogical’ (Hermans, 2011).
    Most of these embodied and extended theories are ego theories, in that
    there is continuity to their proposed selves. But they expand the boundaries
    of the ego so far that the self/other and self/world distinctions begin to dis-
    solve, and it becomes hard to tell where I stop and the world begins. For Andy
    Clark (2008), the self extends beyond the boundaries of consciousness and
    beyond the skin, so that external resources like the information on my phone
    are a central part of my identity. Similarly for Alva Noë, the self is ‘distrib-
    uted’ through the actions that connect my body with objects in the world:
    ‘a person is not a self-contained module or autonomous whole’; a self isn’t
    like a berry, but like the whole plant rooted in earth and tangled in brambles
    (2009, p. 69). This means the senses of unity and continuity no longer need
    explaining in their own right, since they are more closely tied to the unity and
    continuity that characterise the physical and social world in general. And if
    it doesn’t seem this way to us – careful attention to the nature of experience
    may help it to.


CENTRES OF NARRATIVE GRAVITY


Some of the theories considered so far try to explain what the self is  – a work-
ing part of the mental theatre, a special neural process, a strange loop, a mental
model, or a consequence of embodiment or intersubjectivity. Others abandon
the idea of the ‘self itself ’ and try to account only for the feeling we have of having
a self. Some hesitate between these two positions.

‘The other enters


expressions of the self in


their very formulation’


(Gergen, 2011, p. 647)


‘Others think of me


therefore I exist’


(Saunders, 2014, p. 93)


‘consciousness does not


really belong to man’s


individual existence but


rather to his social or


herd nature’


(Nietzsche, 1882/1974, trans.
Kaufmann, §354)


‘My body is an object all


right, but my self jolly


well is not!’


(Farrell 1996, p. 519)

Free download pdf