Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon sIx: seLF AnD otHeR
    attention to experience can lead people to per-
    ceive change occurring but with no apparent
    distinction between past and future (Black-
    more, 2011). This suggests that a search for
    the origins of nowness may be a search for an
    interesting kind of illusion.
    Varela’s ambitions have been taken further
    by a new kind of brain imaging called iGBM
    (intracranial gamma-band mapping), which
    measures gamma-band activity between 40
    and 50 Hz as a general index of neural process-
    ing. It has much greater temporal resolution
    than fMRI, and is precise enough in a single
    trial that the signal-to-noise ratio doesn’t need
    improving by averaging across multiple trials.
    These features make it better for exploring sin-
    gular experiences of individuals. But they also
    demand more precision from those individuals
    if the available resolution is to be useful. Claire
    Petitmengin and Jean-Philippe Lachaux (2013)
    argue that to maximise our chances of inte-
    grating the neural and the experiential, we must attend to the smallest temporal
    unit of experience, changing participants’ focus of attention from what (e.g. what
    they are listening to) to how (how the experience changes over time, how much
    effort is involved, what its effects are, etc.). For them, the study of ‘microdynamics’
    provides access to early and usually invisible stages of our cognitive processes,
    where the distinction between the sensorial modalities, and between the
    ‘subject’ and ‘object’ poles seems to be less rigid than in later stages. We
    hypothesize that these early stages give us a glimpse on the process of
    co-constitution of subject and object, knower and known that is called
    ‘enaction’.
    (p. 5)


To help us understand where neurophenomenology fits into a science of con-
sciousness, Varela (1996) provides a simple diagram with four directions in which
theories of consciousness can go. He positions the best-known thinkers on it, but
excludes quantum theories and dualism, and restricts himself to ‘ “naturalistic
approaches’ ”: those which ‘provide a workable link to current research on cogni-
tive science’ (p. 332). In the north, Varela places functionalist theories, suggesting
that they are the most popular in cognitive science, and that they all rely entirely
on ‘third-person’ data and validation. Opposite them, in the south, are the mys-
terians who claim that the hard problem is insoluble. In the east are the reduc-
tionists, epitomised by the Churchlands, and Crick and Koch, who aim to reduce
experience to neuroscience. Opposite them, to the west, comes phenomenology,
with an area cordoned off for those who believe that a first-person account is
essential, including Varela himself.
This diagram is helpful for thinking about the relationships between different the-
ories, and it also puts a spotlight on the role of first-person approaches in a science

‘I can’t grasp a moment


from which to say that


what has gone before


is past and what is to


come next is future’


(Blackmore, 2011, p. 95)


‘If a bridge is to be built


between the neural and


experiential levels, it


should be done where


the river is shallow,


where descriptions of


mental processes are


fine-grained on both


sides’


(Petitmengin and Lachaux, 2013,
p. 1)


Functionalism

Mysterianism

Phenomenology Reductionism

First-person
accountessential
Bears Dennett

Edelmen

Calvin

Churchland

Jackendoff

Velmans

Varela

Globus
Searle
McGinn Nagel

Crick-Koch

mers

agan
Lekoff-Johns

Consciousness

FIGURE 17.3 • Varela devised this two-
dimensional scheme for
categorising theories of
consciousness. Use it to try to
position as many theories as
you can. Don’t turn the page
until you’ve done it.

Free download pdf