Rotman Management — Spring 2017

(coco) #1

70 / Rotman Management Spring 2017


scholars to shift their focus from examining acts committed
with the intention to do harm to investigations of how individuals
who intend to do good are ultimately tempted to act unethically.
This latter subset of unethical acts can be categorized as ei-
ther intentional (when individuals are cognizant of their ethical
violations) or unintentional (when they are unaware that their
actions cross ethical boundaries). In the domain of intentional
unethical behaviour, the study of ‘behavioural ethics’ — the
systematic and predictable ways in which individuals fail to act
ethically — demonstrates that although there are individual dif-
ferences in people’s moral identity and ethical values, morality
within an individual is also malleable. Mordechai Nisan’s mor-
al balance model shows that people have a ‘moral bank account’,
wherein good deeds ‘raise the balance’ and bad deeds lower it.
Perceptions of a ‘surplus’ in one’s account might lead a person to
cheat, whereas perceptions of a ‘low balance’ might lead one to


act more ethically.
Elsewhere, psychologist James Rest’s model of unethical
behaviour suggests that once an issue has been identified as hav-
ing moral dimensions, individuals engage in a moral judgment
(i.e., they decide whether something is ethical or unethical),
which triggers moral intention (they plan to act either ethically
or unethically) and moral behaviour (they act, either ethically
or unethically). Behavioural ethics research has also shown that
peoples’ judgments, intentions and behaviour depend on the
situational and social forces in the environment. For example, in-
dividuals are more prone to cheat when they feel cognitively de-
pleted and can easily justify their behaviour; and because people
often look to others to determine acceptable norms, people are
also more likely to cheat when they see others cheating.
Alongside the research on intentional acts of cheating is
another body of research that studies how individuals engage in

Are All of Our Good Intentions Just Cheap Talk? By Nina Mažar


Like most of you, I consider myself an honourable member of
society: Trustworthy, honest and moral. Yet I don’t always act ac-
cordingly — and judging by the magnitude of insurance fraud, tax
deception and the illegal downloading of music, films and games,
most of you are like me.
One could say that we are hypocritical. However, to stan-
dard economists, most of what people say is just cheap talk: It’s
meaningless. Only what people do is meaningful: Actions speak
louder than words. This is what economists call, ‘revealed prefer-
ences’, and to an economist, it means that all those who say they
care about morality — but then go ahead and engage in various
transgressions — don’t really care.
To a behavioural scientist like me, the world looks a bit more
complex. We believe that for some of those who say they care
about morality, it’s not just cheap talk: They really mean it. In fact,
we believe that this is true for many people. In short, these people
are good, but they face ‘situational circumstances’ that might
appear unimportant — that they might not even be aware of —
that keep them from being their true ‘authentic selves’. As a con-
sequence, if we make small, smart changes to these situational
circumstances, we may be able to help people behave more
authentically — and act more morally.
To me, this a much better world to live in. Just think about
your own life. I’m sure you can all think of plenty of situations in
which you were tempted to transgress from your moral code
because you could benefit from it. Say, when filling out your tax
form, or an insurance claim. And I bet, in those situations, you
suddenly became very good at rationalizing why it would be okay
to transgress, so that if you did give in, you didn’t feel too bad. We
are very good at rationalizing so that we can ‘have our cake and
eat it, too’ — and it turns out that some situational circumstances
make rationalizations easier to come by than others.

My co-authors and I recently teamed up with a car insur-
ance company in the U.S. This company regularly sends out ‘audit
forms’, asking policy holders to indicate the odometer mileage
for their cars. Insurance premiums are then adjusted to corre-
spond with how much a car is driven. The logic is, ‘the more miles
driven, the more likely an accident, and the higher the insurance
premium’.
As a result, when policy holders receive the audit form, many
are tempted to under-report their mileage. Almost immediately,
their rationalizations start working: ‘I already pay such a high
insurance rate!’ I’m not the problem, I’m a good driver’. Suddenly,
they are under-reporting their mileage, and not feeling bad about
it at all. And by the time they reach the end of the form — where
they are asked to confirm with their signature that they have filled
it out truthfully — they have managed to convince themselves
that everything is indeed legit.
By comparison, in a court of law, people are asked, up front,
to swear that they will ‘tell the truth, the whole truth, and nothing
but the truth’. Only then do they testify. In short, we ask people to
commit to being truthful before, not after they face temptations
to misreport. This is a very interesting twist, because such a pre-
commitment to the truth is likely to increase people’s attention
to their own moral standards — to keep them top of mind, and
therefore, harder to ignore in the face of temptations. If this is the
case, we posited, perhaps we could use this insight to redesign
those insurance audit forms.
That’s exactly what we did: We randomly assigned a policy
holder to either receive the standard audit form (with a signature
field at the end), or a form that was identical except for one thing:
the signature field was moved to the top. The result: Policy hold-
ers who signed the audit form at the top magically seemed to be
driving more; on average, 2,500 miles more per car. To put this in
Free download pdf