The Price of Prestige
lily
(lily)
#1
132 chapter five
assume that governments are more interested in the potential value of the
inventor than in the often unintelligible results of the scientist. Since basic-
science projects offer few tangible applied implications, they cannot be eas-
ily explained as strategic investments. In material terms, the closer a proj-
ect gets to the “science” pole, the more it resembles a “pure Veblen good,”
and the more puzzling it becomes to those that ignore its signaling quali-
ties. The strategic investment argument, therefore, fails to explain many
Big Science cases, including the transits of Venus races explored below.
Big Science as a Promoter of Knowledge
If Big Science is taken at face value, then the main object of these proj-
ects is the accumulation of scientific knowledge. According to such in-
terpretation, governments fund Big Science because they value scientific
knowledge. Yet, such an explanation quickly succumbs to the collective
action problem. Science tends to produce knowledge that is accessible
to all, both domestically and internationally. Domestically, the “public
good” qualities of scientific research often lead to market failures that
can only be solved by governmental investment in R & D (Stiglitz 1999 ;
Stigler 1971 ).^8 However, when we move to the international level, govern-
ments find themselves locked into a similar collective action problem, this
time with no “world government” to intervene and regulate international
funding for basic research. Why should the French government invest in
basic research when German scientists are likely to benefit from that re-
search as well? Hence, a country that funds basic research is providing an
international public good (Solingen 1993 , 45 ). While most governments
are likely to prefer a world with greater knowledge, they are also likely to
prefer that someone else pay for it. This should lead to free riding and
suboptimal levels of funding. Consequently, the theoretical puzzle is not
why governments shy away from funding “pure” science projects, but why
they would ever pay for such projects, not to mention compete over the
right to do so.
Indeed, governmental investment in basic research tends to be con-
siderably lower than governmental investment in applied sciences. In the
end of the 1920 s, for example, the United States provided $ 200 million a
year to applied sciences compared with only $ 10 million for basic research;
only four thousand American scientists were involved in basic research
compared with thirty thousand scientists engaged in applied science. Her-
bert Hoover used the logic of free riding to explain this discrepancy: “We
have depended on three sources — that the rest of the world would bear this