Identity A Very Short Introduction (Very Short Introductions)

(Steven Felgate) #1
Signs and objects

In everyday discourse, we use sentences of this synthetic form all the time,
connecting two expressions with ‘is’. The identity relation thus asserted has
three properties. It is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive.


Reflexive:


(2)         Aristotle   is  Aristotle   (identical  with    himself).

Symmetric:


(4)         If  Aristotle   is  the son of  Nicomachus, then    the son of  Nicomachus  is
Aristotle.

For transitivity we need another predicate, for instance, ‘a student of Plato’s
academy’, and arrive at the following.


Transitive: and


(5)         If  Aristotle   is  Nicomachus’ son,    and Nicomachus’ son is  a   student of
Plato’s academy, then Aristotle is a student of Plato’s academy.

It is well known that Aristotle joined Plato’s academy, but only when he was 16
or 17 years old. Is (5) therefore false? If so, the substitution test would be
imperfect.


This raises the question of ‘sense and reference’, the title of a famous treatise by
logician Gottlob Frege (1848–1925), Über Sinn und Bedeutung, which deals
with the problem of identity of meaning as it comes to bear when considering
sentences such as (2), (4), and (5). If a and b are objects—Aristotle and
Nicomachus’ son, respectively—it is unsatisfactory (paradoxical) that a is
sometimes identical with b, and sometimes not. Frege argues that, therefore, an
identity statement ‘ ’ must be conceived as a relation holding between signs
rather than objects:


Nobody  can be  forbidden   to  use any arbitrarily producible  event   or  object  as  a   sign    for something.  In
Free download pdf