The Economics Book

(Barry) #1

195


See also: Economic man 52–53 ■ Risk and uncertainty 162–63 ■ Paradoxes in decision making 248–49 ■ Behavioral
economics 266–69


Maurice Allais challenged this
theory from what he referred to as
the American School of economics.
He pointed out that expected
utility theory is based on an
assumption, known as the
independence axiom, that says
people will dispassionately look at
the likelihood of outcomes and the
utility they will gain from each one.
In particular, they will view each
choice independently, ignoring any
factors that are common to each
option. Allais said that this was
rarely, if ever, true. His contention
became known as the Allais paradox.


Irrational choice
We cannot directly see people’s
thought processes when they choose,
but we can observe the choices they
make and see if these are consistent
with rationality and the independence
axiom. Imagine that you are given a
choice between an apple and an
orange, and you choose the apple.
Now imagine that you are offered the
choice of an apple, an orange, and a
peach. The independence axiom
assumes that you might choose the


apple again, or the peach, but you
would not choose the orange—
because the addition of the peach
cannot change your preference for
apples over oranges.
The violations of independence
that Allais detected, however, take
place in situations of uncertainty.
Suppose you had a choice between
two “lotteries,” each of which has
several possible outcomes with
particular probabilities. The first
lottery gives you a 50 percent
chance of an apple and a 50 percent
chance of a peach. The second
lottery gives you a 50 percent
chance of an orange and a 50
percent chance of a peach. Because
you prefer apples to oranges, you
should choose the first lottery:
under the independence axiom,
the addition to each lottery of a
peach—making the peach equally
probable as an outcome in both
choices—should make no difference
to the choice of apple over orange.
But in practice, very often it does.
In experiments using more
complex forms of this kind of
choice, people frequently violate

POST-WAR ECONOMICS


the independence axiom. This
conflicts with the standard
economic idea that humans always
act rationally. For some reason the
presence of other choices in a set of
options seems to matter to people—
it makes a difference. The discovery
of these kinds of behaviors has
spawned the new field of behavioral
economics (pp.266–69), which
attempts to devise more
psychologically realistic models
of decision making. ■

Maurice Allais Maurice Allais was born in Paris,
France, in 1911. His father died
during World War I, and this
affected Allais deeply. He excelled
at school and studied mathematics
at the elite École Polytechnique,
graduating first in his class in


  1. He then served in the
    military before working first as an
    engineer, then as departmental
    manager for the École Nationale
    Supérieure des Mines. During this
    time he also published his first
    pieces on economics. In 1948, the
    École Nationale allowed him to
    focus entirely on teaching and
    writing, and he became their


professor of economic analysis.
A polymath, Allais also made
contributions to physics. In
1978, he was the first economist
to be awarded a gold medal by
France’s National Centre of
Scientific Research, and in 1988,
he won the Nobel Prize for
economics. He died in 2010.

Key works

1943 In Search of an Economic
Discipline
1947 Economy and Interest
1953 The Behavior of Rational
Man Confronting Risk

Whatever their attraction
might be, none of the
fundamental postulates
forumulated by the American
School can withstand analysis.
Maurice Allais
Free download pdf