Immigration and open borders
N
o country in the world operates an ‘open
borders’ policy. All control their borders.
But the extent to which immigrants are
welcomed and the criteria for citizenship vary
considerably between them. Two major princi-
ples govern citizenship laws: (a) jus sanguinis, or
determination through the family line; (b) jus
soli, or determination through place of birth.
The second principle also allows for the acquisi-
tion of citizenship by individuals who have no
family connection with the country, whereas the
first principle precludes this possibility.
Some political theorists argue for open
borders. Joseph Carens argues that if a person’s
gender, race or social class is rejected as a valid
ground for discrimination then it follows that
membership of a particular society should also
be treated as a morally irrelevant fact. Carens
acknowledges that there is a ‘general case for
decentralization of power’ which would justify
the existence of ‘autonomous political commu-
nities comparable to modern states’ (1995: 335).
The question is whether such communities
should have the right to limit entry and exit. If
free movement within a state is justified then it
follows that unhindered movement between
states must be legitimate.
Is Carens right? Should there be any
restrictions on immigration? If restrictions
are justified what should be the criteria for
citizenship? Should an individual have to prove
an historical family connection to the country?
Should only skilled workers be admitted? Should
the families of new citizens get automatic
citizenship? Is ethnicity ever a legitimate ground
for determining citizenship?
© Mike Kemp/In Pictures/Corbis