Introduction to Political Theory

(Marvins-Underground-K-12) #1

function of the state is coercively to police territorial boundaries, and for ethnic
nationalists the absence of a territory makes the reproduction of a group’s genes
very difficult.
J. Philippe Rushton claims that nationalism – or ‘ethnic nepotism’ – can be
explained by the ability of individuals to detect genetic closeness, or similarity. He
provides a range of empirical evidence for the general theory of genetic similarity
(Rushton, 1989, 2005), although these claims have been criticised (criticisms are
indicated in the parentheses):



  1. Sexually interacting couples who produce a child together are more alike
    genetically than those who do not. (But ‘mate choice criterion templates’ are
    acquired from parents such that men might tend to marry the image of their
    mothers (Daly, 1989: 520).)

  2. Non-romantic friends also tend to be similar and similarity is greatest on the
    most heritable traits. (Friends may be similar on relatively heritable traits merely
    because genotypes systematically seek environments to which they are adapted
    (Gangestad, 1989: 525); for example, genes determine height, strength and
    stamina and so people with similar genotypes might end up together in a sports
    team – they are not selecting each other because of the similarity of their genes
    but because of what their genes produce.)

  3. Alcoholics are attracted to alcoholics and there are other similar ‘negative’
    features that give rise to attraction. (However, people may settle for similar others
    because they have no choice in the mating game and not because they are selecting
    the same genes; and if genetic similarity theory is an attempt to explain why like
    attracting like is adaptive why would attraction also hold for ‘negative’ traits?
    (Economos, 1989: 521).)
    As a general point, Rushton has to show, first, that the average degree of
    relatedness between mates (and also friends) is higher than it is in the population
    as a whole, and, second, choices are made on the basis of genetic similarity. Finding
    the right control group (‘population’) is difficult. Proximity could explain mating.
    Most people marry people who live – and were born – close by. It follows that the
    correct control group should be from a circumscribed – localised – community
    (Graves and Byrne, 1989: 527). To test whether we recognise genetic similarity in
    others it has to be restricted to times when only unrelated but genetically similar
    individuals will be encountered. It is hard to see the circumstances under which this
    would happen (Hepper, 1989: 530).
    Frank Salter (2002) has drawn on Rushton’s genetic similarity theory in
    producing a normative political theory in which nationhood promotes a person’s
    ‘genetic interests’. There are not distinct races with hard boundaries between them
    but there are degrees of genetic closeness. What is particularly interesting about
    Salter’s approach is that he takes the gene to be not only the basic unit of inheritance,
    but also the primary unit of value. As we mentioned above evolutionary biologists
    have debated at what level Darwinian selection takes place, with possible candidates
    being the gene, the organism (e.g. individual human beings) or the group (of which
    there could be various kinds). Traditional nationalists might be thought to be
    concerned exclusively with the group, while liberals think that only the individual
    is important. Salter, however, believes our interests lie in the reproduction of our


Chapter 12 Nationalism 273
Free download pdf