Introduction to Political Theory

(Marvins-Underground-K-12) #1

  • The tu quoquedefence was removed – ad hominem tu quoquemeans ‘at the
    person, you too’ and effectively amounts to the defendant saying ‘you committed
    the same crimes, so you have no authority to judge me’.

  • The indictment made reference to violations of ‘international conventions’, but
    there is no citation of those conventions, with the implication that it was a loose
    term meaning the ‘general standards of criminal law in civilised societies’.
    Although the motivation among the leadership of the Allied powers to create the
    Nuremburg process was largely political, there was a moral consciousness at work,
    a consciousness that became stronger in later decades. Consequently, Nuremberg
    posed a problem: on the one hand there was a sense of what can be termed the
    ‘objective wrongness’ of what the German regime had done. On the other hand,
    the trials seemed to depend on the creation of post hoc, or retroactive, laws.
    Retroactive laws violate the principle that there can be no crime without an
    antecedent law: if you do something that is legal at the time of doing it, then you
    should not later be prosecuted for that act. If retroactive laws are created then
    power is arbitrary (other ‘troubling’ aspects of Nuremberg included the rejection
    of both the tu quoqueand compulsion defences). There has been considerable
    debate among legal and political theorists about the retroactivity problem; some
    theorists argue that German law was suspended at a point during the 1930s, and
    therefore the laws of Weimar Germany (1918–33) should form part of the basis of
    the indictment. Other theorists appeal to conventions, such as the prohibition on
    murder, which all ‘right-thinking’ human beings, and all properly functioning legal
    systems, recognise as valid.
    The point about Nuremberg is that German law of the Nazi period could not
    form the basis of the judgment, and so other laws or conventions, not rooted in a
    particular legal system, had to be used. And Nuremberg is not simply an interesting
    historical problem, because it has relevance for contemporary debates about human
    rights: if there are human rights as defined at the beginning of this section, then
    they are universal, and the universality extends across national boundaries and
    across times. The Nuremberg problem will not disappear when the last alleged Nazi
    war criminal has died, for it is fundamentally a philosophical problem: how can
    there be human rights if there are no laws embodying those rights? But if human
    rights only exist where there are laws stating those rights, then how can they be
    universal? The post-Nuremberg codification of human rights in the UDHR and the
    Genocide Convention (1948) helps to solve a legal problem, but not the
    political–philosophical one. To explain, the UDHR was (eventually) signed by the
    governments of most states, and through the force of treaty law human rights have
    been given legal validity. Had there been such a declaration in the 1920s to which
    Germany had signed up, and that was not rescinded by the Hitler regime, then there
    would have been a clearer legal basis for Nuremberg (there was such a basis for
    the third count of war crimes: the Geneva Conventions of 1864, 1906 and 1929).
    However, this does not solve the philosophical problem: if a nation refuses to sign
    up to any human rights conventions does that mean it is not obliged to respect
    human rights?
    This question – and the distinction between legal and philosophical problems –
    reveals an ambiguity at the heart of human rights discourse. When we use the term
    ‘human rights’ are we referring to a set of legal rights, or to moral rights, or, perhaps,


404 Part 4 Contemporary ideas

Free download pdf