Famine
Singer on famine
How individuals and states respond – or should respond – to famine throws into
sharp relief central issues in the global justice debate. Peter Singer, in an influential
article (1972), argues that if you are passing a pond and see a drowning child then
so long as you are not in danger of sacrificing something morally equivalent to that
child’s life you have an obligation to wade in and save the child. There may be a
cost to you – perhaps you will ruin your expensive suit – but that cost has to be
weighed against the loss of a life, and in the balance it is clear what you should
do. The failure to make a significant financial contribution to relieve famine on the
other side of the world is in all important respects no different to the refusal to
jump in and save the drowning child.
Singer’s argument is, on the face of it, very simple and he seeks to build it on
two assumptions that any reasonable person would accept: (a) ‘suffering and death
from lack of food, shelter, and medical care are bad’; (b) ‘if it is in our power to
prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of
comparable moral importance, we ought, morally, to do it’ (Singer, 1972: 231).
Proximity to suffering is irrelevant – the child starving 7,000 kilometres away is no
less important than the child drowning 50 metres from you. The potential number
of rescuers is of no moral significance – that potentially millions could help the
starving child but only you could save the drowning child may alter howyou assist
but not that you shouldassist. Imagine that you are among a group of onlookers
seeing the child drowning: that others could help but are not helping in no degree
reduces your responsibility to save the child. That there are millions of potential
donors capable of relieving a famine does not reduce your obligation to donate to
famine relief.
There are, of course, coordination problems in the case of famine that – assuming
you are the only potential rescuer – do not exist in the pond example. The cost of
saving the drowning child can be calculated as the loss of your $1,000 suit, while
the costs of relieving famine are less clear. If we are all willing to give whatever is
required to end the famine but lack communication we may end up giving too
much. However, the existence of a mass media solves this problem. And prisoner’s
dilemma-type situations do not arise here, because we are assuming that we have
a moral obligation to help, such that even if nobody else gave any money you should
still donate. The only sense in which the non-donors are ‘free-riding’ on your
donation is that they are relying on youto fulfil theirobligations to the starving.
Sen on famine
To explore the problems with Singer’s argument I will contrast it with another
discussion of famine, advanced by Amartya Sen. Sen’s work is not a response to
Singer and the two explorations of famine are different rather than mutually
incompatible: Singer is advancing an argument in moral philosophy about our
Chapter 22 Global justice 483