Notes to Pages 254-261 481
duced Kraus's translation of an essay on influenza by a certain Fothergill that had
appeared in the Gentleman's Magazine of February 1776 (see Ak 8, pp. 6-8). This
Introduction and the circumstances surrounding its writing is interesting in the
context of Kant's lifelong fascination with medicine as well as his relationship with
a member of the faculty of medicine at the University of Königsberg.
- Ak 10, p. 271.
- Ak 10, p. 273.
- Hamann, Briefwechsel, IV, p. 319, see also pp. 323, 331.
- Hamann, Briefwechsel, IV, p. 336.
- Hamann, Briefwechsel, IV, p. 341; see also pp. 344, 350. For further details see Ak 4,
pp. sg8f.
- Hamann, Briefwechsel, IV, pp. 376, 400, 418.
- Kant, Prolegomena, p. 123 (Ak 4, p. 374). Thus the second edition of his first
Critique, like many of the textbooks and popular treatises of the time, contains a
"Refutation of Idealism," but quite unlike most of these, it lacked a "Refutation
of Skepticism."
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. 123 (Ak 4, p. 374). This position comes close to
his own view in the Inaugural Dissertation. Though sensitive knowledge is not
"sheer illusion" in the Inaugural Dissertation, the ideas of the pure understand¬
ing and reason (which are not clearly differentiated in the Inaugural Dissertation)
are the only genuine parts of metaphysics.
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, pp. iof. (Ak 4, pp. 26of.).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, pp. 6f. (Ak 4, pp. 258f).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. 5 (Ak 4, p. 257).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. 67 (Ak 4, p. 320).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. 80 (Ak 4, p. 332).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, pp. io8f. (Ak 4, pp. 359^).
- Hume, Enquiries, pp. nf.
- Hume, Enquiries, pp. 26f, 44m
- Hume, Enquiries, p. 16.
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. no (Ak 4, p. 361). See also Bxxiv: "on a cursory
view of the present work it may seem that its results are merely negative, warning
us that we must never venture beyond the limits of experience. Such is in fact
its primary use ... So far as our Critique limits speculative reason, it is indeed
negative."
- Hume's principle is today perhaps better known by P. F. Strawson's name: "Kant's
principle of significance." It is, as he says, a principle "with which empiricist
philosophers have no difficulty sympathizing." Kant's "espousal of the principle
of significance and in his consequential repudiation of transcendent metaphysics,
Kant is close to the tradition of classical empiricism, the tradition of Berkeley and
Hume." "Kant's principle of significance" is a principle of meaning for Strawson.
Kant was not necessarily concerned with meaning per se. See P. F. Strawson, The
Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (London: Methuen,
1966), p. 16.
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, p. 104 (Ak 4, p. 356).
- Kant, Prolegomena, ed. Beck, pp. iO4f. (Ak 4, pp. 356f).