The Philosophy of Psychology

(Elliott) #1

some degree, but apparently without consciousness. And Block (1995)
describes cases of epileptics who continue their activities when undergoing
a mildWt, but who do so without conscious awareness. Indeed, the psycho-
logical literature is nowrifewith examples of non-conscious perceptual
processing, including the equivalent of blindsight in other sense-modalities



  • ‘deaf-hearing’, ‘insensate-touch’, and so on (see Baars, 1988, and Weis-
    krantz, 1997, for reviews).
    Furthermore, it seems highly likely that beliefs and desires can be
    activated without emerging in conscious thought processes. Consider, for
    example, a chess-player’s beliefs about the rules of chess. While playing,
    those beliefs must be activated – organising and helping to explain the
    moves made and the pattern of the player’s reasoning. But they are not
    consciously rehearsed. Chess-players will not consciously think of the rules
    constraining their play, except when required to explain them to a begin-
    ner, or when there is some question about the legality of a move. Of course
    the beliefs in question will remainaccessibleto consciousness – players can,
    at will, recall and rehearse the rules of the game. So considered as standing
    states (as dormant beliefs), the beliefs in question are still conscious ones.
    We have nevertheless shown that beliefs can be non-consciously activated.
    The same will hold for desires, such as the desire to avoid obstacles which
    guides my movements while I drive absent-mindedly. So thoughts as
    events, or mental episodes, certainly do not have to be conscious.
    Essentially the same point can be established from a slightly diVerent
    perspective, by considering the phenomenon of non-conscious problem-
    solving. Many creative thinkers and writers report that their best ideas
    appear to come to them ‘out of the blue’, without conscious reXection
    (Ghiselin, 1952). Consider, also, some more mundane examples. I might
    go to bed unable to solve some problem I had been thinking about
    consciously during the day, and then wake up the next morning with a
    solution. Or while writing a paper you might be unable to see quite how to
    construct an argument for the particular conclusion you want, and so
    might turn your conscious attention to other things. But when you come
    back to it after an interval, everything then seems to fall smoothly into
    place. In such cases you must surely have been thinking – deploying and
    activating the relevant beliefs and desires – but not consciously.
    One thing which a good theory of state-consciousness needs to do, then,
    is to provide a satisfying explanation of the distinction between conscious
    and non-conscious mental states, explaining what it is about the various
    phenomena in question which makes them fall on one or other side of the
    divide.


Preliminaries: distinctions and data 233
Free download pdf