217
SMITH, ADAM
such as authenticity, purity, and openness
carry something of the meaning of sin-
cerity. To be insincere is to speak or act
with a lack of openness because the world
of inner states is hidden from the conver-
sation partner or the external observer.
An inauthentic person similarly exhibits
a kind of deceitfulness, either toward
others (internal states are deliberately
hidden and incongruent external states
are exhibited), or within oneself by per-
mitting self-deception (an inconsistency
among internal states which is masked
either deliberately or unconsciously).
Sincerity is considered a virtue, but in
much contemporary usage it is a fairly
“thin” or “flat” virtue without much robust
content. One could fail in terms of many
more important virtues but still be
accorded the virtue of sincerity (with the
implication that in most other ways the
person fails and is misguided). But not
just any congruence between inner and
outer states can be called sincere. Thus, it
would be odd to speak of someone as
“sincerely cruel.” This suggests an addi-
tional factor of some type of purity which
is a grounding for sincerity or to which
sincerity as a virtue is tethered. This con-
dition of purity (in some relevant sense)
seems to be invoked when, instead of
individual actions, a person is character-
ized as sincere. Sincerity has waxed and
waned as an aesthetic virtue in Western
literature. In the eighteenth century it
began to be prized as an aesthetic quality
so that poetry, for example, was judged to
be better if it possessed sincerity in the
sense that it matched inner states of the
poet, or arose from appropriate authentic
inner states. Later, due in part to the noto-
riously difficult business of ascertaining
authorial intention, sincerity became
much less important aesthetically.
SKEPTICISM. There is a sense in which
no philosophy, let alone philosophy of reli-
gion, is possible without some skepticism.
When Augustine professed to believe in
the God of Christianity he was, in essence,
being skeptical about the gods of Imperial
Rome. As Augustine and Descartes noted,
there are degrees of skepticism. Modest
forms of skepticism make sense in certain
contexts, but it is more problematic when
skepticism is projected universally. For
example, if someone who claims to be a
skeptic charges that no person knows any-
thing, it appears that the “skeptic” is not
really skeptical, but is making a radical
claim that reaches almost breath-taking
proportions. Can one know that no one
has ever known anything? To answer this
in the negative would seem to require a
Herculean task of examining every possi-
ble knower. And then if the person did
claim to know that no one knows any-
thing, the person would seem to refute her
own position for (if she is right) then she
knows something (and thus she is wrong).
SMITH, ADAM (1723–1790). Scottish
economist and philosopher, Smith