MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
To help, or to do no harm 103

questions such as the following: Are therapeutics and medicine identical?

Or is therapeutics a part of medicine, or perhaps an aim (or eventheaim)

of medicine? Or is therapy just one among several different activities the

doctor carries out? And how are the various components, or methods, of

therapy interrelated? Do they all have the same purpose, and are they all

considered to be equally important? Is there a special status for dietetics

(which does not necessarily aim athealing)? The answers to these questions

are by no means obvious, yet they are of fundamental importance to an

understanding of what Greek doctors of this period were up to and what

they believed the purposes of their activities to be.

As is well known, in sections 5 – 8 of the proem Celsus discusses the

early period when the medical art was – in Celsus’ view perniciously –

incorporated within the theoretical study of the nature of things (rerum

naturae contemplatio) and he presents, with obvious approval, Hippocrates

as the one who emancipated medicine out of the bondage of philosophy

(studium sapientiae), the pursuit of knowledge for its own sake, which Celsus

claims to be so fundamentally harmful to the body:

Ergo etiam post eos de quibus rettuli, nulli clari uiri medicinam exercuerunt donec


maiore studio litterarum disciplina agitari coepit ( 6 ) quae, ut animo praecipue


omnium necessaria, sic corpori inimica est. Primoque medendi scientia sapien-


tiae pars habebatur ut et morborum curatio et rerum naturae contemplatio sub


isdem auctoribus nata sit, ( 7 ) scilicet iis hanc maxime requirentibus qui corpo-


rum suorum robora quieta cogitatione nocturnaque uigilia minuerant. Ideoque


multos ex sapientiae professoribus peritos eius fuisse accipimus, clarissimos uero


ex his Pythagoran et Empedoclen et Democritum. ( 8 ) Huius autem, ut quidam


crediderunt, discipulus, Hippocrates Cous, primus ex omnibus memoria dignus,


a studio sapientiae disciplinam hanc separauit, uir et arte et facundia insignis.^5


After those, then, of whom I have just spoken, no man of any fame practised


the art of medicine until literary activity began to be practised with greater zeal,


( 6 ) which, while being most necessary of all for the mind, is also harmful to the


body. At first the knowledge of healing was regarded as a part of wisdom,^6 so that


both the treatment of diseases and the study of natural things came into being


under the same authorities, ( 7 ) clearly because those who most required it [i.e.


medicine] were those who had weakened the strength of their bodies by their


sedentary thinking and their wakeful nights. For this reason, as we hear, many


of those who claimed expertise in wisdom were experienced in it [i.e. medicine],


the most famous of them indeed being Pythagoras, Empedocles, and Democritus.


( 8 ) But a pupil of this last, as some believed him to be, Hippocrates of Cos, the


(^5) Text according to Serbat ( 1995 ) 3 – 5.
(^6) Sapientiaclearly covers both science and philosophy.

Free download pdf