MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
172 Aristotle and his school

also in philosophers like Democritus and, perhaps, Heraclitus, in which

sleep was viewed positively as a state in which humans, or at least some of

us, are capable of modes of cognition not open to us in the waking state

and in which we enjoy a special receptivity to experiences, impulses or, as

Aristotle would put it, ‘movements’ (kin ̄eseis) that we do not receive, or at

least are not aware of, during the waking state; and there are elements of this

in Aristotle’s theory too. These experiences and impulses can be subdivided

into stimuli that have their origin within the dreamer and those that come

from outside.^9 The internal stimuli are the ones arising from the dreamer’s

body, or from his/her internal experiences, memories, thoughts, imagina-

tions or emotions; and these are the stimuli that were of particular interest

to medical writers, such as the author of the Hippocratic workOn Regimen

just mentioned, and to philosophers (like Aristotle) interested in the rela-

tion between the psychological and the physiological aspects of sleep. The

external stimuli can in their turn be subdivided into two categories: those

that have their origin in the natural world, and those that come from the

supernatural (gods, demons, etc.);^10 and this group of external stimuli was

of particular interest to thinkers such as Democritus (and, again, Aristotle)

trying to find an explanation for the phenomenon of prophecy in sleep

concerning events that lie beyond the dreamer’s direct experience.

A similar, related ambivalence surrounded the question whether the

sleeping life of an individual presents a complete negation of the character

and personality of his/her waking life, or whether there is some connection

or continuity between the two states. It would seem that if one defines

sleep negatively (as Aristotle does) as an incapacitation of our powers of

consciousness, the consequence would be that in the sleeping state the

characteristics of our individual personalities are somehow inactivated: it

would be as if, in sleep, we lose our identity and temporarily become like a

plant. Yet, paradoxically, this negative view also allowed a positive valuation

of the state of sleep. For it can be argued that in sleep our souls or minds

are released from our bodies (and from experiences associated with the

body, such as perception and emotion) and acquire a temporary state of

detachedness and purity, thus anticipating the state of the immortal soul

after its definitive detachment from the body after death. This latter view –

that in sleep the soul is set free from the body and regains its ‘proper

nature’ (idia phusis) – was especially found in Orphic and Pythagorean

thought, with its negative view of the body and its dualistic concept of

the relation between soul and body, and found its expression in stories

(^9) See Aristotle,Insomn. 460 b 29 – 30 ;Div. somn. 463 a 3 – 30 ; 463 b 1 – 2 ; 463 b 22 – 3 ; 464 a 15 – 16.
(^10) SeeOn Regimen 4. 87 ( 6. 640 – 2 L.); cf. Arist.,Somn. vig. 453 b 22 – 4 (but on the interpretation of the
termdaimoniosthere see below, pp. 187 , 191 , and 246 – 7 with n. 30 ).

Free download pdf