MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
182 Aristotle and his school

refers explicitly in 463 a 4 – 5 ), and perhaps also from literary descriptions

of dreams such as were found in Homer and the epic tradition. However,

since this tradition has only been preserved in fragments, it is difficult to

assess the extent of his dependence on earlier sources.

Yet when looking more closely at the way in which these empirical

‘data’ are used in Aristotle’s argument inOn Dreams, it becomes clear that

the treatise goes far beyond the level of empirical fact-finding. Aristotle

does not present his theory as being built up, so to speak, inductively on

the basis of a number of observations; on the contrary, the three research

questions mentioned above ((i), (ii) and (iii)) are treated in a systematical

and deductive way, and empirical ‘data’ are mentioned in the course of this

theoretical argument – often in the form of examples or analogies – in

order to support or clarify opinions and presuppositions which Aristotle

already seems to take for granted. And although Aristotle’s style of reasoning

seems very cautious and essayistic – the first chapter, for example, is highly

aporetic^25 – it is, in fact, rather dogmatic. The general impression one gets is

that empirical evidence is primarily mentioned when it suits the argument –

and if not, it is either ignored or explained away in a questionable manner.

Thus at the end ofOn Dreams, it turns out that the three questions raised

at the beginning are to be answered as follows:

(i) Dreams belong to the sensitive part of the soulquaimaginative part

( 459 a 21 ); dreaming is not an operation of sense-perception but of ‘imag-

ination’, which is defined by Aristotle as ‘the movement which occurs as

a result of actual perception’ ( 459 a 17 – 18 ). This definition, together with

Aristotle’s use of the wordsphantasia,phantasma, andphainesthai,isin

broad agreement with his general theory of ‘imagination’ inOn the Soul,

to which he explicitly refers ( 459 a 15 ). In the course of the long argument

which leads to this conclusion, only claims ( 1 ) and ( 2 ) play a part; for the

rest, the argument is purely theoretical and logical.

(ii) How do dreams come into being? Aristotle assumes the following

mechanism: During the waking state, the sense-organs are stimulated by

a great quantity of sense-movements (stimuli brought about by sensible

objects); but not all of these movements are equally strong. The stronger

movements overrule the weaker, so that the weaker are ‘not noticed’ by the

perceiving subject ( 460 b 28 – 461 a 8 ). Aristotle assumes, however, that the

remnants of these weaker movements remain present in the sense-organs

in the form of traces. When in sleep the sense-organs have stopped being

active – and as a result of this cannot receive new stimuli – the remnants of

(^25) For an analysis see van der Eijk ( 1994 ) 36 – 8.

Free download pdf