MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
190 Aristotle and his school

The rationale for this seems to be as follows. If the gods really granted

knowledge of the future to humans, they would distribute this knowledge

according to the extent to which people meet the criterion of ‘being beloved

by the gods’, and this means for Aristotle that a person should realise his/her

moral and intellectual virtues to the highest degree and thus approach the

divine level.^29 However, Aristotle argues, we can observe that prophetic

dreams in reality occur also (or, exclusively) with simple-minded people,

who stand on a lower moral level, and even to animals, who do not even

have reason and thus lack the capacity to realise virtue.Ergo: dreams cannot

be sent by a god.^30

Aristotle thus presupposes that people with low moral and intellectual

capacities are particularly susceptible to prophetic dreams. His favourite

example is the melancholics, whom he mentions twice because of their

remarkable foresight (cf. chapter 5 above). He explains this by reference to

their physiological constitution, which brings about a certain receptivity

to a large number and variety of appearances: the chance that they meet

with a phantasm which resembles an actual future state of affairs is, from

a statistical point of view, greater than with other people. It is entirely

unclear how Aristotle arrived at this view (there are no antecedents of this

characteristic of the melancholics in medical literature).^31 It seems, rather,

that we have a case of ‘wishful thinking’ on the part of Aristotle here (and

perhaps an extrapolation of his own dreaming experiences). Of course, his

theory allows for prophecy in sleep to occur with intelligent people as well,

but then we are dealing with cases where the origin of the event foreseen in

the dream lieswithin the dreamer(for example, an action (s)he is going to

perform, a physical disturbance which is going to befall him/her and which

announces itself through another physical manifestation, namely, a dream).

But in those cases where the future event foreseen in the dream occurs, for

example, at the other end of the world, this must be a coincidence due

to the multiplicity of images befalling the melancholics in their sleep, he

seems to say.

The second presupposition underlying Aristotle’s reasoning here is of a

teleological kind: if some dreams can be shown not to be of divine origin,

then this applies to all dreams. In this way, Aristotle anticipates two possible

counter-arguments one might raise, namely that it is not necessary thatall

dreams are god-sent, or that it is not necessary thatalldreams are prophetic.

This kind of classification of various types of dreams is already found in

(^29) Cf.Eth. Nic. 1179 a 21 – 30 , discussed below in ch. 8.
(^30) For a parallel argument concerning ‘good fortune’ ( () see ch. 8 below.
(^31) See ch. 5 above.

Free download pdf