MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Aristotle on the matter of mind 231

the body;^80 and there may be other medical influences as well,^81 especially

of dietetics, for it was certainly one of the claims of dietetics in Aristotle’s

time to provide a physiologically founded doctrine of ‘the good life’.^82 The

Peripatetic school was very receptive to these medical views, as is shown,

for example, by theProblemata physica, and Aristotle was almost certainly

aware of them. Now it is certainly true that Aristotle’s psychology is much

richer and much more sophisticated than that of the medical literature, but

it should not be overlooked that there is also a ‘technical’ side to Aristotle’s

psychology, an interest in the ‘mechanics’ of cognition and in modalities

of thinking such as concentration, analytical powers, creativity, quickness

() of thinking and intuition ("

0 (),^83 habituation


and repetition, anddegreesin capacities to all these activities. It very rarely

comes to the surface inOn the Soul, but it figures more prominently in

theParva naturaliaand in the zoological works, mostly when one species

of animals is compared with another or when different members of one

species are compared with one another, and mostly in contexts in which

some sort of disturbance or aberration in cognitive behaviour is discussed.

It is in these contexts that bodily factors are made responsible for these dis-

turbances or aberrations; Aristotle does not explain what thenormalbodily

conditions for a normal functioning of thinking are, and they can only be

deduced indirectly. However, it is very likely that the concept of ‘the mean’

plays an important part here.^84

This situation provides a parallel (though not a solution) to another

problem in Aristotle’s theory of thinking – which has recently received

much attention and which has already been alluded to above – namely the

question of animal intelligence.^85 In many (although admittedly not all)

of the passages in which Aristotle seems to credit animals with intellectual

capacities he compares one species with another, and in this comparative

perspective man is simply seen as the most intelligent (the use of com-

paratives such as

 
or superlatives such as

in


these contexts is striking). Here, too, there seems to be a tension between

a ‘relativistic’, biological view of man as a=*nat the end of a scale which

(^80) For a discussion of these chapters see the commentary by Joly and Byl ( 1984 ). See also Jouanna ( 1966 )
and Hankinson ( 1991 b) 200 – 6.
(^81) The cognitive role of the blood reminds us, of course, of Empedocles (see Kullmann ( 1982 ) 230 ).
The doctrine ofpneumamay be inspired by Diocles of Carystus (see Longrigg ( 1995 ) 441 ).
(^82) See Tracy ( 1969 ),passim. On the claims of dietetics, and its relation to philosophy in the fourth
century see also G. W ̈ohrle ( 1990 ), chs. 4 and 5.
(^83) Cf.An. post. 89 b 10 ff.;Eth. Nic. 1142 b 3 – 6 ;Rh. 1362 b 24 ; 1412 a 13 ;To p. 151 b 19 ;Div. somn. 464 a 33.
(^84) On this see the excellent discussion by Tracy ( 1969 ).
(^85) For a survey of the recent discussion see Coles ( 1997 ).

Free download pdf