MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
244 Aristotle and his school

moral), and thus the degree of excellence found in the people among whom

eutuchia, or divination in sleep, or any other phenomenon commonly at-

tributed to divine dispensation, occurs, actually becomes for Aristotle a

criterion by which he judges whether this attribution is correct. Just as the

fact that ‘happiness’ (eudaimonia) is found with the ‘wise’ (thesophoi), who

are ‘most beloved by the gods’ (theophilestatoi), supports the idea that it is

granted by the gods, likewise the fact thateutuchiaoccurs with people who

are not ‘wise’ and do not possess excellence furnishes an argument against

the idea thateutuchiais given by the gods. This is consistent with Aristotle’s

remark (Div. somn. 464 a 20 ; see above) that if foresight of the future were

given by the gods, they would give it ‘during the daytime’ (meth’ h ̄emeran),

not at night; for at night the faculty in virtue of which good people can be

distinguished from bad people is inactive.^23

This whole complex of thought on the relationship between a ‘divine

concern’ (theia epimeleia) and human moral qualification – irrespective of

whether there is such a thing as divine concern at all – is firmly rooted

in Aristotle’s ethics, as is shown by the passages cited above (to which

might be addedEth. Eud. 8. 3 , 1249 b 3 – 23 ).^24 It is clear, therefore, that

the distribution argument is not simply an occasional, or even (as was

claimed by Dirlmeier) an un-Aristotelian argument,^25 and it is all the more

surprising that this argument does not pose an impediment to Aristotle’s

conclusion thateutuchiais ‘divine’ (theia)in 1248 b 4.

The first part of the solution to this problem is in that the ‘movement’ of

God in the fortunate men (the ( who succeed without reasoning,

'

\  $
), as described in 1248 a 25 ff., is not regarded by


Aristotle as a form of ‘divine concern’ (  


). The idea which is


labelled as ‘paradoxical’ (')in 1247 a 28 – 9 is that a god or demon

‘loves’ (

 ) a man who does not possess reason (!): the emphasis


is on ‘loving’ no less than on ‘a god or demon’ ( 3 B  ). But in his

(^23) Cf.Eth. Nic. 1102 b 3 – 11 ;Eth. Eud. 1219 b 19 ff.;Mag. mor. 1185 a 9 ff.
(^24) See especially 1249 b 16 ff.: the man who makes such a choice of the ‘natural goods’ (-
" )
that they advance the contemplation of God possesses the best standard for the practical life; this
is ‘the wise man’ ( !). I follow the interpretation of this passage offered by Verdenius ( 1971 )
292 : ‘When God has revealed himself through the channel of contemplation, his influence gets the
character of a directive power. This directive power is turned towards practical action through the
intermediary of!#
.’ The fact that this standard () consists in ‘paying as little attention as
possible to the irrational part of the soul’ (3 Z
 
  
$ "!(or:') 
 :) is in marked contrast with 1248 a 40 : ‘It seems that this starting-point is more powerful
when reason has been disengaged’ (
 1 8 "% "  $ !
-
 +).
(^25) Dirlmeier ( 1935 ) 60 – 1 ‘Sie geh ̈ort noch dem suchenden Aristoteles an, ja sie ist gar nicht aristotelisch,
sondern platonisch.’ But Dirlmeier also labelsEth. Nic. 1162 a 5 and 1179 a 23 ff. as ‘un-Aristotelian’.
See also Vidal ( 1959 ) 179.

Free download pdf