MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Introduction 21

and a readiness to take documents such as the Dervenyi papyrus, the in-

troduction of Parmenides’ poem and thePurificationsof Empedocles more

seriously. Similar ‘paradigm’ shifts have taken place in the study of Hip-

pocratic medicine, and there is now a much greater willingness among

interpreters^25 to accept the religious and ‘rational’ elements as coexistent

and – at least in their authors’ conception – compatible. The question is not

so much to disengage from their mythical context those elements which we,

or some of us, regard as philosophically interesting from a contemporary

perspective, but rather to try to see how those elements fit into that context.

Within this approach, the author ofOn the Sacred Diseasecan be regarded

as an exponent of a modified or ‘purified’ position on traditional religious

beliefs without abandoning those beliefs altogether and, as such, he can be

said to have contributed also to the development of Greek religious or the-

ological thought; for his arguments closely resemble those found in Plato’s

‘outlines of theology’ in the second book of theRepublic, or, as I said above,

Aristotle’s arguments against the traditional belief that dreams are sent by

the gods in hisOn Divination in Sleep(see also chapter 6 ).

One further, paradoxical aspect ofOn the Sacred Diseaseand its alleged

‘rationality’ is worth mentioning here. On the one hand, it is probably

the best known of all the Hippocratic writings after theOath, and its

author (who is widely agreed to be also the author ofAirs, Waters, Places)

has often been regarded as one of the most plausible candidates for being

identical with the historical Hippocrates. On the other hand, this is a fairly

recent development, which stands in marked contrast to the rather marginal

position the treatise occupied in ancient perceptions of Hippocrates. It

hardly figures in ancient lists of Hippocratic writings, and it is particularly

striking for its almost complete absence from Galen’s references to the

Hippocratic Corpus. This is all the more remarkable considering that it is

by far the most suitable piece of evidence for Galen’s claim that Hippocrates

held an encephalocentric view of the mind (see chapter 4 ); there is even

a suggestion that Galen may have regarded the treatise as spurious. This

indicates the changeability of assessments of a treatise’s importance and

representativeness, and hence the danger of using ancient evaluations as

evidence in the so-called ‘Hippocratic question’.

5 medicine beyond ‘hippocrates’

I have already touched on the great diversity among the writings attributed

to Hippocrates and, at some time long after they were written, assembled

(^25) See, e.g., Jouanna ( 1998 ) and ( 2003 ); and Hankinson ( 1998 c).

Free download pdf