Comp. by: VPugazhenthi Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_H Date:1/4/
09 Time:15:18:22 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/
revises/9781405132879_4_H.3d
In the twentieth century, the German phil-
osopher Martin Heidegger (1889–1976) took
Dilthey’s epistemological rendering of her-
meneutics and transformed it into an onto-
logical one, making its focus ‘being’ rather
than ‘knowledge’ (cf.epistemology;ontol-
ogy). The details are complex, but the gist is
that problems of understanding unfold from
our ‘being in the world’. Just as the hermen-
eutic circle for Dilthey involved tacking be-
tween parts of a text and its whole, for
Heidegger it involves a movement between
an anticipatory pre-understanding, which
comes from our ‘being-ness’’, and our role as
knowing subjects. Hans-Georg Gadamer
(1900–2002) subsequently took Heidegger’s
notion of pre-understanding and showed its
relation to notions of prejudice, authority and
tradition. Since theenlightenment, Gadamer
argued, there has been prejudice against preju-
dice. For him, however, ‘pre-judgement’, or
pre-judice, is what makes understanding pos-
sible. In particular, the prejudices of historical
‘traditions’ are vital; without immersion in tra-
ditions, there is no understanding. It is not
that traditions are frozen and immutable:
Gadamer’s point is that we can never escape
traditions and the historical perspective that
they bring. Historical understanding proceeds
by a movement from our prejudices (tradi-
tions) to the historical totality and back, mak-
ing understanding ‘an open and continuously
renewed ‘‘fusion’’ of ‘‘historical horizons’’’
(Thompson, 1996, p. 381).
Gadamer’s work, in turn, provoked two
other formulations. First, the German critical
theorist Ju ̈rgen Habermas (b. 1929) thought
that Gadamer made humans too much the
dupes of historical tradition. Consequently,
he developed acritical theoryofsociety
by setting hermeneutics against quasi-
transcendental forms of ‘communicative rea-
son’ that in conjunction produce the possibil-
ity of emancipation and liberation. Second,
American philosophers Richard Rorty (1931–
2007) and Richard Bernstein, writing under
the sign of neo-pragmatism, were sceptical of
Gadamer’s claim that hermeneutics wasthe
method of the human sciences, but acknow-
ledged its importance for the critique ofgrand
theoryand other forms offoundationalism
(thus connecting hermeneutics to post-
structuralism). Both Rorty and Bernstein
upheld the pragmatist ideal of ‘conversation’,
which they believed was another version of the
hermeneutic circle, in this case, juxtaposing
new evidence and ideas with existing and pos-
sibly incommensurate ones.
Hermeneutics was introduced tohuman
geographyto contest the empiricism and
positivismfound inspatial science. Butti-
mer’s (1974) ‘dialogical approach’, which in-
volved bringing together inside and outside
views, was an important early contribution,
as were Tuan’s (1971) reflexive approach to
topophilia(‘to know the world is to know
oneself’) and Harrison and Livingstone’s
(1980) ‘presuppositional approach’. These
early forays were codified underhumanistic
geography, which made human meaning and
intentionality the very core of its concern.
Since then, the explicit working out of the
hermeneutical approach has become less im-
portant, although there have been some ex-
ceptions, such as Barnes’ (2001) invocation
in his work on thecultural turnwithineco-
nomic geographyand Livingstone’s (2002c)
writings on a distinctly ‘tropical hermeneutics’
(seetropicality). In addition, hermeneutics
has been implicitly present in the burgeoning
discussions aboutontology, especially those
drawing upon Heidegger, and which in turn
have seeped into debates aroundspatiality.
More generally, the spirit of hermeneutical
enquiry – that is, the recognition of the im-
portance of interpretation, open-mindedness
and a judicious, reflexive sensibility – is
as great as it has ever been, and is certainly
evident in critical human geography,
including those versions informed bypost-
structuralism. tb
Suggested reading
Bernstein (1983).
heteronormativity A social regulatory
framework that produces binarysexdivision,
normalizes desire between men and women,
and marginalizes othersexualitiesas different
and deviant. Much likewhiteness, heteronor-
mativity is naturalized so as to be invisible to
the heterosexual population, but is a compul-
sory norm that itself produces nature;
namely, bodies sexed as male or female.
Reversing the assumed relations between sex
andgender, Butler (1990) has argued that
heteronormativity is the foundation on which
sexual difference is built. Predicated on the
paternal law of kinship, heteronormativity
‘requires conformity to its own notions of
‘‘nature’’ and gains its legitimacy through
the binary and asymmetrical naturalization
of bodies’ (Butler, 1990, p. 106: seeperfor-
mativity). Bodies outside this binary are un-
intelligible or monstrous. Berlant has argued
that in the USA in the past 20 years, the
Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_H Final Proof page 329 1.4.2009 3:18pm
HETERONORMATIVITY