The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: VPugazhenthi Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_S Date:1/4/
09 Time:15:23:35 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/
revises/9781405132879_4_S.3d


to a global-to-local continuum that under-
writes the problematic view that social pro-
cesses can be detached from the grounded
sites where people and objects concretely
reside and social practices take place (e.g. in
streets, bedrooms, boardrooms). They offer
in its place aflat ontologythat resists concep-
tualizing processes as operating at scales that
hover above these sites (e.g. metropolitan
regions, nation-states). This view continues
to generate much debate (e.g. Leitner and
Miller, 2007; Jones, Woodward and Marston,
2007). sam/kw/jpj

Suggested reading
Jones, Woodward and Marston (2007); Leitner
and Miller (2007); Marston (2000); Marston,
Jones and Woodward (2005); Sheppard and
McMaster (2004).

science/science studies Science is an
‘essentially contested concept’ (Gallie, 1964)
in the sense that it defies specification in
terms of necessary and sufficient conditions.
Numerous candidates have been offered by
philosophy to discriminate science from
non-science – knowledge based on first-hand
observation, claims and procedures warranted
by predictive success, the inductive gathering
of empirical data, information satisfying the
principles of verification or falsification,
and so on. The efforts of Copernicus and
Galileo to base knowledge on causal explan-
ations rather than Aristotelian syllogism,
Bacon’s plea for inaugurating the method of
induction, Newton’s rejection of speculative
hypotheses in favour of his own method of
deduction (see hypothesis), the Logical
Positivists’ emphasis on thelogicalstructure
of theories (see logical positivism), and
Lakatos’ defence of what he called ‘the meth-
odology of scientific research programmes’
constitute just a few of the proposals that have
been made to place science on secure founda-
tions (Oldroyd, 1986). But none of these have
been adequate to catch the presumed essential
features of enterprises that stretch temporally
from Aristotle to Einstein, cognitively from
astronomy to zoology, and spatially from medi-
eval Arabic geodesy to Enlightenment Scottish
chemistry. This recognition has led to what
Larry Laudan (1988) has aptly termed ‘the
demise of the demarcation problem’. Uncon-
tested mapping of the border between science
and other forms of human cultural activity (see
culture)hassimplyremainedelusive.
Nevertheless, the label ‘science’ does refer
to a suite of enterprises sharing some family

resemblance with the kinds of observational
and experimental practices that came to char-
acterize natural philosophy during the period
of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
(seescientific revolution(s)). And it was in
that era that the term itself began to acquire
a definition that linked it to a body of demon-
strated truths and observed facts brought
into coherence by their adherence to general
natural laws. As Watts put it in 1725 (2, ii, §9),
the word ‘science’ was ‘usually applied to
a whole body of regular or methodical obser-
vations or propositions’.
geography’s engagements with the scientific
tradition have been multi-faceted. Termino-
logically, the label ‘scientist’ has close associ-
ations with geography via Mary Somerville,
whosePhysical geographyof 1848 firmly staked
geography’s claims to scientific status. In fact, it
was in a review of one of her earlier books that
the word ‘scientist’ was first coined by William
Whewell (that irrepressible neologist), although
it did not circulate into common currency until
the 1870s. Historiographically, insights from
the philosophy and history of science have been
used by a range of geographers to interpret
the evolution of their own tradition of enquiry
(seegeography, history of). In particular, the
perspective of Thomas Kuhn on the structure
of scientific revolutions has been the subject of
discussion within the discipline as to the extent
to which it throws light on Geography’s lineage
(see alsoparadigm).
In two other substantive ways, Geography
and science are tightly interwoven. First, geo-
graphical practice has routinely – though cer-
tainly not universally – adopted scientific
techniques and vocabulary, and not just in
physical geographywith its evident roots in
both field andlaboratoryscience. Thus dur-
ing the period of the Scientific Revolution, for
example, mathematical advances were used to
solve problems ofmap projection, and the
subject was routinely taught in association
with astronomy. In the same period,
Varenius’Geographia generalisof 1650 advanced
his own version of the mechanical philosophy
to contest Aristotelianism, and William
Petty began to apply the methods of the new
natural philosophy to social phenomena with
his development of ‘political arithmetick’.
Navigational expertise, requiring computa-
tional skills and knowledge of observational
astronomy, was also often taught in geography
courses (Livingstone, 2003b). Such projects
firmly linked geography as an enterprise
to practical mathematics and the scientific
tradition, and this impulse has continued to

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_S Final Proof page 666 1.4.2009 3:23pm

SCIENCE/SCIENCE STUDIES
Free download pdf