Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_C Date:31/3/09
Time:21:45:52 Filepath://ppdys1108/BlackwellCup/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-
9781405132879/appln/3B2/revises/9781405132879_4_C.3d
production and the centralization of capitalist
control under the figure of the capitalist-
entrepreneur. These claims – to the extent that
they reflect some common ground – are sub-
sequently elaborated in radically different
ways. Some cling to a narrow definition of
economy (theorized in different ways) as
central to the intellectual enterprise; others
seek to link economy,culture, politics and
societyinto a more elaborated sense – what
Max Weber called a ‘cosmos’ – of a capitalist
system. In general, the development and
institutionalization of the critical social sci-
ences has seen a massive proliferation of
opinion – and of conceptual apparatuses – for
the examination of actually existing capitalist
systems.
Some of this diversity of opinion can be
appreciated by a consideration of a quartet of
theorists. Adam Smith, like other classical
political economists, was concerned with the
distribution and accumulation of economic
surplus and the problems of wage, price and
employment determination. Writing at the
birth of industrial manufacture, the key to
theWealth of nations(see Smith, 2003) is the
concept of an autonomous self-regulating
market economy described ascivil society.
Smith’s genius was to have seen the possibility
of an autonomous civil society, its capacity for
self-regulation if left unhindered and its cap-
acity for maximizing welfare independent of
state action. Smith located capitalism at the
intersection of thedivision of labourand
the growth of markets. Furthermore, in this
system self-interested individuals indirectly
and inadvertently promoted collective interest
through the functions of self-regulating mar-
kets. The growth of commerce and the growth
of liberty reinforce one another under capital-
ism. In its neo-classical variant, labour mar-
kets are seen as no different than any
commodity market and capitalist markets are
assumed, if unimpeded by the state or other
distortions, to function to produce a general
equilibrium. Friedrich von Hayek’s (1944)
account of liberal capitalism took this reason-
ing to its limit. Capitalism was conceived of as
a unity of liberty, science and the spontaneous
orders that co-evolved to form modern society
(the ‘Great Society’, as he termed it). It is a
defence of the liberal (unplanned) market
order from which the preconditions of civiliza-
tion – competition and experimentation – had
emerged. Hayek, like Weber, saw this modern
world as an iron cage constituted by imperson-
ality, a loss of community, individualism and
personal responsibility. But, contra Weber,
these structures, properly understood, were
the very expressions of liberty. From the
vantage point of the 1940s this (classical) lib-
eral project was, as Hayek saw it, under threat.
Indeed, what passed for liberal capitalism was
a travesty, a distorted body of ideas warped by
constructivist rationalism, as opposed to what
he called ‘evolutionary rationalism’. Milton
Friedman (2002 [1962]), in the realm of eco-
nomic theory, waged this battle from the
1960s onwards.
For Max Weber, the capitalist cosmos was
guided by systems of calculability and ration-
ality – this is what gave Western capitalism its
specificity – which grew in part as an unin-
tended consequence of Protestantism (see
Weber, 2001 [1904–5]). Formal rationality
produced a capitalist society characterized by
large-scale industrial production, centralized
bureaucratic administration and the ‘iron
cage’ of capitalism that shapes individuals’
lives with ‘irresistible force’.ContraSmith’s
roseate vision of capitalism – though always
wary of the costs of class oppression, in his
view dished out by corrupt government –
Weber’s vision of capitalism was ultimately
bleak, always operating in the shadow of the
‘totally administered society’.
Karl Polanyi was a Hungarian economic
historian and socialist, who believed that the
nineteenth-century liberal capitalist order had
died, never to be revived (see Polanyi, 2001
[1944]). By 1940, every vestige of the inter-
national liberal order had disappeared, the
product of the necessary adoption of measures
designed to hold off the ravages of the self-
regulating market; that is, ‘market despotism’.
It was the conflict between the market and the
elementary requirements of an organized
social life that made some form of collectivism
or planning inevitable. The liberal market
order was,contraHayek, not ‘spontaneous’
but a planned development, and its demise
was the product of the market order itself. A
market order could just as well produce the
freedom to exploit as the freedom to associate.
The grave danger, in Polanyi’s view, was that
liberal utopianism might return in the idea of
freedom as nothing more than the advocacy of
free enterprise, in which planning is ‘the denial
of freedom’, and the justice and liberty offered
by regulation or control just ‘a camouflage of
slavery’. liberalism on this account will
always degenerate, ultimately compromised
by an authoritarianism that will be invoked as
a counterweight to the threat of massdemoc-
racy. Modern capitalism, he said, contained
the famous ‘double-movement’ in which
Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_C Final Proof page 60 31.3.2009 9:45pm
CAPITALISM