The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
8 6

cH A Pt eR 5 ■ D e e p A n a l y s i s

form a chain of simpler arguments that culminate in the ultimate conclusion,
but only after some intermediate steps. Consider this argument:

There’s no way I can finish my paper before the 9 o’clock show, since I have
to do the reading first, so I won’t even start writing until at least 9 o’clock.
It might seem tempting to put this argument into standard form as:
(1) I have to do the reading first.
(2) I won’t even start writing until at least 9 o’clock.
∴(3) I can’t finish my paper before the 9 o’clock show. (from 1–2)
This reformulation does include all three parts of the original argument, but it
fails to indicate the correct role for each part. The two argument markers in the
original argument indicate that there are really two conclusions. The word “since”
indicates that what precedes it is a conclusion, and the word “so” indicates that
what follows it is also a conclusion. We cannot represent this as a single argu-
ment in standard form, because each argument in standard form can have only
one conclusion. Thus, the original sentence must have included two arguments.
The relationship between these arguments should be clear: The conclusion of the
first argument functions as a premise or reason in the second argument. To repre-
sent this, we let the two arguments form a chain. This is the first argument:
(1) I have to do the reading first.
∴(2) I won’t even start writing until at least 9 o’clock. (from 1)
This is the second argument:
(2) I won’t even start writing until at least 9 o’clock.
∴(3) I can’t finish my paper before the 9 o’clock show. (from 2)
If we want to, we can then write these two arguments in a chain like this:
(1) I have to do the reading first.
∴(2) I won’t even start writing until at least 9 o’clock. (from 1)
∴(3) I can’t finish my paper before the 9 o’clock show. (from 2)
This chain of reasoning can also be diagrammed like this:
(1)

(2)

(3)

The arrows indicate which claims are supposed to provide reasons for which
other claims. Because these premises and arrows all fall on a single line, it is
natural to call this structure linear.

97364_ch05_ptg01_079-110.indd 86 15/11/13 9:53 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf