The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
9 3

so m e st a n d a r d s f o r ev a l u a t i n g A r g u m e n t s

Now compare this argument:
(1) Either Joe or Jack or Jim or Jerry committed the murder.
(2) Joe did it.
∴(3) Jerry did not commit the murder. (from 1–2)
To show that this argument is invalid, all we have to do is explain how the
premises could be true and the conclusion false. Here’s how: Joe and Jerry
did it together. In that case, Jerry did it, so the conclusion is false; Joe also
did it, so the second premise is true; and the first premise is true, because it
says that at least one of these four suspects did it, and that is true when more
than one of the suspects did it. That possibility of complicity, thus, makes
this argument invalid.
We will explore many more forms of argument in Chapters 6 and 7. The
goal for now is just to get a feel for how to determine validity. In all of these
examples, an argument is said to be valid if and only if there is no possible
situation in which its premises are true and its conclusion is false. You need
to figure out whether there could be any situation like this in order to deter-
mine whether an argument is valid. If so, the argument is invalid. If not, it
is valid.
This definition shows why validity is a valuable feature for an argu-
ment to possess: There can be no valid argument that leads one from true
premises to a false conclusion. This should square with your commonsense
ideas about reasoning. If you reason well, you should not be led from truth
into error.
What are known as deductive arguments are put forward as meeting this
standard of validity, so validity is one criterion for a good deductive argu-
ment. Other arguments—so-called inductive arguments—are not presented
as meeting this standard. Roughly, an inductive argument is presented as
providing strong support for its conclusion. The standards for evaluating
inductive arguments will be examined in Chapters 8-10. For now, we will
concentrate on deductive arguments.

Truth


Although a deductive argument must be valid in order to be a good argu-
ment, validity is not enough. One reason is that an argument can be valid
even when some (or all) of the statements it contains are false. For example:
(1) No fathers are female.
(2) Sam is a father.
∴(3) Sam is not female. (from 1–2)
Suppose that Sam has no children or that Sam is female, so premise 2 is false.
That would be a serious defect in this argument. Nonetheless, this argument
satisfies our definition of validity: If the premises were true, then the conclu-
sion could not be false. There is no way that Sam could be female if Sam is a

97364_ch05_ptg01_079-110.indd 93 15/11/13 9:53 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf