The Sociology of Philosophies

(Wang) #1
Hume; in fact Whitehead’s discussion of these thinkers largely focuses on the flaws
of their sensationism and intellectualism. Leibniz, the thinker whom he most closely
resembles, receives relatively few explicit references. Whitehead and Alexander in
effect recapitulate the positions of Leibniz and Spinoza in terms of twentieth-cen-
tury scientifically oriented Idealism.


  1. A phenomenon noted for all historical periods by sociologists of religion (Stark
    and Bainbridge, 1985; Finke and Stark, 1992).

  2. Kuklick (1977: 135–136; 234–235). Royce had come as a graduate student to
    Hopkins from Berkeley, where Gilman had been president before Hopkins; he was
    introduced to Idealism by Hopkins’s G. S. Morris, who also taught John Dewey.
    During the customary sojourn in Germany, Royce studied with Lotze, Wundt, and
    Windelband. Characteristically for the Americans of this period, his own philoso-
    phy was more Idealist than that of his German professors.

  3. James’s changing disciplinary identification may be traced in his successive titles:
    assistant professor of physiology in 1876, assistant professor of philosophy in
    1880, and professor in 1885; professor of psychology in 1889; back to professor
    of philosophy in 1897 (Boring, 1950: 510–511).

  4. For this reason Peirce regarded mathematics as the investigation of the conse-
    quences of hypotheses; he himself innovated mathematical notation similar to the
    work of Dedekind and Cantor (DSB, 1981: 10:484).

  5. Buchler (1955: 354, 356). Peirce pointed out that an infinite regress results when
    one attempts to analyze certain kinds of relations: a statement of relation must
    always characterize the relation of relations to their subjects, and so on. The
    argument parallels Bradley, except that from Peirce’s mathematical viewpoint, such
    nested series of relations fit the definition of the continuum “as that in which every
    part is of the same nature as the whole” (EP, 1967: 6:76).

  6. Brent (1993: 311, 300, 209); Buchler (1955: 323). Eisele (DSB, 1981: 10:485)
    summarizes: “Nature syllogizes, making inductions and abductions.”

  7. This is confirmed by the pattern of the various European analogues to pragmatism.
    In Germany, Mach interpreted scientific laws as practical fictions; and indeed James
    met and admired Mach during a visit to the Continent in 1882, long before
    formulating his own pragmatist doctrine (Johnston, 1972: 181). Vaihinger’s Phi-
    losophy of As-If (1911) similarly resonates with James. But the aims are quite
    different from James’s religious concerns. Mach’s positivism is purely scientific, and
    Vaihinger is a Neo-Kantian concerned with the validity of the forms of experience
    in the absence of a thing-in-itself. Pragmatism never became a self-conscious
    movement in Germany as it was in the United States. In the German university
    orbit the generations of Idealists had long since passed, and there was no demand
    for such a stepping-stone between religious Idealism and secularism. Where we do
    find the analogue to the United States is in Italy, where a pragmatist movement,
    led by Calderoni, arose soon after the zenith of Idealism. Here the timing was like
    that in America: the university system was under reform, as secularizers wrested
    it from the hands of the church and installed a German-style educational system.
    The Italian pragmatists were a halfway house between positivism and Idealism,
    criticizing both schools while borrowing elements from both.


Notes to Pages 672–678^ •^1011
Free download pdf