MUSIC, PHILOSOPHY, AND MODERNITY

(Tuis.) #1
390 music, philosophy, and modernity

the issue of perlocution apparent.^13 Unlike illocutionary effects, per-
locutionary effects cannot, then, be construed in terms of ‘an accepted
conventional procedure having a certain conventional effect’ (ibid.:
180 ). At the same time – and this is the crux – it is essential to human
communication that I can still ‘rationally expect’ to have perlocutionary
effects on you, such as inspiring you, or irritating you, because other-
wise ‘I would lack the capacity to make myself intelligible to you. And
what you would lack is not some information I might impart to you’
(ibid.). Making oneself intelligible, then, involves a fundamental con-
tingency, but it also involves rational expectation. Both the contingency
and the rational expectation are based on the knowledge that language
does things to people. In this sense the refusal to give priority to the
representational aspects of language can itself be regarded as having
an ethical significance.
It is not hard to relate some of this to music, which cannot achieve its
effects simply by convention, and which would in many circumstances
not be music at all if one could not expect that it will have effects on
those who hear it. Music admittedly cannot be described as ‘perlocu-
tionary’ in a literal sense, because it is not achieving effects through
the speaking or writing of words. However, Cavell’s remarks on the
role of gesture in speech make the translation from language to music
unproblematic in this context. The vital factor here is thecombination
in both language and music of a potential for having effects which can
be anything from dangerous to life-enhancing, with the possibility that
the same expression that gives rise to such effects could also amount
to nothing, because it elicits no response. I shall consider in a moment
what follows from the fact that some perlocutionary verbs can and some
cannot be applied to music.^14 The significance of music here derives
not least from the fact that many ‘perlocutionary’ effects, in the sense
of what results from human expressions which engage and affect their
recipients in emotional and ethical ways – or indeed proto-cognitive
ways, as when one senses, by the way they play music, the particular
emotional state of someone who is reserved – cannot be achieved by
words at all. These considerations about what language and music can
do which is not primarily descriptive or cognitive can put in question
one aspect of Rorty’s conviction that ‘the notion of something real but

13 Fears about demonic musical virtuosity in the nineteenth century can be interpreted in
the light of the nature of perlocution.
14 In the case of those that can be applied it is important that there is no necessary identity
between what the word conveys and what the music may actually do.

Free download pdf