Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy

(C. Jardin) #1

discovery of acknowledged facts, it loses some of its trenchancy, its arbitrariness, and
becomes the “discovery” of the solution that isimmanentin the situation. Machiavelli
becomes a scientist: the Sovereign becomes a lab technician; the word “decision”
changes meaning and no longer alternates between the sovereign arbitration of the
facts and the arbitrariness of the Sovereign.



  1. In Chapter 5, I shall come back to this essential definition of the enemy that
    must not be humiliated because it might become an ally. In effect, we are going to make
    it a synonym for externalization
    .

  2. The Plato ofGorgias,still close to the political capacities that he is in the process
    of stifling one by one, uses the superb expression “autophuos,” self-generation (513b) to
    describe and mock this immanence particular to the conditions of felicity of public life
    (Latour 1999b). On this vocabulary of sophistics, see Cassin 1995. John Dewey trans-
    lated this skill particular to politicians most directly with his very reflexive notion of
    “public,” an artificial elaboration that models for itself the unexpected consequences of
    its actions (Dewey 1954 [1927]).

  3. We can measure once again the difference between society and the collective;
    the notion of society, so cherished by sociologists of the social,eliminatesin advance all
    the problems of composition, modelization, reflexivity, and agitation that I am obliged
    to deploy one after the other. With the transcendence of nature already there and that
    of society always already present as a totality, neither the skill of scholars nor that of
    politicians is visible.

  4. On this difference in the two regimes of enunciation, see Latour 2002b.

  5. Polanyi 1944, 249: “After a century of blind ‘improvement’ man is restoring his
    ‘habitation.’”

  6. In John Dewey’s sense (Dewey 1954), that is, as something that has to be con-
    stantly refreshed and, so to speak, re-represented to its own eyes, since experts are ex-
    actly as blind as citizens as to the unexpected consequences of collective action.

  7. This reversal had already been carried out by the beginning of the last century
    by Gabriel Tarde, in a book as little known as it is astonishing, on “passionate interests”
    (Tarde 1902).

  8. By extending Simmel’s reflection on money, one can imagine, moreover, that the
    generalization of the numerical will offer “social metaphysics” other possible summa-
    ries besides the language of money. See, for example, the fascinating effort in “cyber-
    geographies” in Rogers and Marres 1999. If we follow them, we note that economics is
    not necessarily the definitive form for publicizing calculations and hierarchies.

  9. On externalities, I am following here the introductory essay of Callon 1998b and
    the political consequences drawn in Callon, Lascoumes, et al. 2001.

  10. This whole argument is comprehensible only on condition that we take the term
    “calculation” literally and not metaphorically: either one can carry out a calculation,
    and accounting instruments in the broad sense are required, or else these instruments
    are lacking and the ties in question remainincalculable;see Callon and Latour 1997.
    This is what precludes any metaphorical use of “calculation” or “economic capital,” es-
    pecially to explain social life (Favereau 2001).

  11. The economists alternate between excessive modesty and excessive pretension:
    if one praises the intensity of their influence on the economy, they humbly claim to


NOTES TO PAGES 146–153
275
Free download pdf