The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course

(coco) #1
324 11. POST-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY

Third, in connection with the extension of these locus problems, Pappus con-

siders the locus to more than six lines and says that a point satisfying the corre-

sponding conditions is confined to a definite curve. This step was important, since

it proposed the possibility that a curve could be determined by certain conditions

without being explicitly constructible. Moreover, it forced Pappus to go beyond the

usual geometric interpretation of products of lines as rectangles, thus pushing the

same boundary that Heron had gone through. Noting that "nothing is subtended

by more than three dimensions," he continues:

It is true that some of our recent predecessors have agreed among

themselves to interpret such things, but they have not made a

meaningful clear definition in saying that what is subtended by

certain things is multiplied by the square on one line or the rec-

tangle on others. But these things can be stated and proved using

the composition of ratios.

It appears that Pappus was on the very threshold of the creation of the modern

concept of a real number as a ratio of lines. Why did he not cross that threshold?

The main reason was probably the cumbersome Euclidean definition of a composite

ratio, discussed in Chapter 10. But there was a further reason: he wasn't interested

in foundational questions. He made no attempt to prove or justify the parallel

postulate, for example. And that brings us to the fourth attraction of Book 7. In

that book Pappus investigated some very interesting problems, which he preferred

to foundational questions. After concluding his discussion of the locus problems, he

implies that he is merely reporting what other people, who are interested in them,

have claimed. "But," he says,

after proving results that are much stronger and promise many

applications,.. .to show that I do not come boasting and empty-

handed. .. I offer my readers the following: The ratio of rotated

bodies is the composite of the ratio of the areas rotated and the

ratio of straight lines drawn similarly [at the same angle] from

their centers of gravity to the axes of rotation. And the ratio of

incompletely rotated bodies is the composite of the ratio of the ar-

eas rotated and the ratio of the arcs described by their centers of

gravity.

Pappus does not say how he discovered these results, nor does he give the

proof. The proof would have been fairly easy, given that he had read Archimedes'

Quadrature of the Parabola, in which the method of exhaustion is used. For the

first theorem it would have been sufficient to compute the volume generated by

revolving a right triangle with one leg parallel to the axis of rotation, and in that

case the volume could be computed by subtracting the volume of a cylinder from

the volume of a frustum of a cone. If the theorem is true for two nonoverlapping

areas, it is easily seen to be true for the union of those areas. Pappus could then

have applied the method of exhaustion to get the general result. The second result

is an immediate application of the Eudoxan theory of proportion, since the volume

generated is obviously in direct proportion to the angle of rotation, as are the

arcs traversed by individual points. The modern theorem that is called Pappus'

theorem asserts that the volume of a solid of revolution is equal to the product of
Free download pdf