The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course

(coco) #1
540 19. LOGIC AND SET THEORY

properties of number, under another that of a geometrical problem,
and under a third that of optics.

Here Boole, like de Morgan, was arguing for the freedom to create abstract
systems and attach an interpretation to them later. This step was still something
of an innovation at the time. It was generally accepted, for example, that irrational
and imaginary numbers had a meaning in geometry but not in arithmetic. One
could not, or should not, simply conjure them into existence. Cayley raised this
objection shortly after the appearance of Boole's treatise (see Grattan-Guinness,
2000, p. 41), asking whether it made any sense to write ^x. Boole replied by
comparing the question to the existence of which he said was "a symbol (i)
which satisfies particular laws, and especially this: i^2 = —1." In other words, when
we are inventing a formal system, we are nearly omnipotent. Whatever we prescribe
will hold for the system we define. If we want a square root of —1 to exist, it will
exist (whatever "exist" may mean).
Logic and classes. Although set theory had different roots on the Continent, we
can see its basic concept—membership in a class—in Boole's work. Departing from
de Morgan's notation, he denoted a generic member of a class by an uppercase X,
and used the lowercase ÷ "operating on any subject," as he said, to denote the
class itself. Then xy was to denote the class "whose members are both X's and
Ys." This language rather blurs the distinction between a set, its members, and the
properties that determine what the members are; but we should expect that clarity
would take some time to achieve. The connection between logic and set theory is an
intimate one and one that is easy to explain. But the kind of set theory that logic
alone would have generated was different from the geometric set theory of Georg
Cantor, which is discussed in the next section.
The influence of the mathematical theory of probability on logic is both exten-
sive and interesting. The subtitle of de Morgan's Formal Logic is The Calculation
of Inference, Necessary and Probable, and, as noted above, three chapters (some
50 pages) of Formal Logic are devoted to probability and induction. Probability
deals with events, whereas logic deals with propositions. The connnection between
the two was stated by Boole in his later treatise, An Investigation of the Laws of
Thought, as follows:

[T]here is another form under which all questions in the theory
of probabilities may be viewed; and this form consists in substi-
tuting for events the propositions which assert that those events
have occurred, or will occur; and viewing the element of numerical
probability as having reference to the truth of those propositions,
not to the occurrence of the events.

Two events can combine in different ways: exactly one of Å and F may occur,
or Å and F may both occur. If the events Å and F are independent, the probability
that both Å and F occur is the product of their individual probabilities. If the two
events cannot both occur, the probability that at least one occurs is the sum of
their individual probabilities. More generally,


P(E or F) + P(£and F) = P(E) + P{F).

When these combinations of events are translated into logical terms, the result is
a logical calculus.

Free download pdf