The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

(Michael S) #1

Defining and Revising the Structure of Evolutionary Theory 87



  1. I affirm the importance and high relative frequency of spandrels, and
    therefore of nonadaptive origin, in evolutionary theory by two major arguments for
    ubiquity. First, for intrinsic structural reasons, the number of potential spandrels
    greatly increases as organisms and their traits become more complex. (The
    spandrels of the human brain must greatly outnumber the immediately adaptive
    reasons for increase in size; the spandrels of the cylindrical umbilical space of a
    gastropod shell, by contrast, may be far more limited, although exaptive use as a
    brooding chamber has been important in several lineages.) Second, under
    hierarchical models of selection, features evolved for any reason at one level
    generate automatic consequences at other levels—and these consequences can only
    be classified as cross-level spandrels (since they are "injected into" the new level,
    rather than actively evolved there).

  2. The full classification of spandrels and modes of exaptation offers a
    resolving taxonomy and solution—primarily through the key concept of the
    "exaptive pool"—for the compelling and heretofore confusing (yet much
    discussed) problem of "evolvability." Former confusion has centered upon the
    apparent paradox that ordinary organismal selection, the supposed canonical
    mechanism of evolutionary change, would seem (at least as its primary overt
    effect) to restrict and limit future possibilities by specializing forms to complexities
    of immediate environments, and therefore to act against an "evolvability" that
    largely defines the future macroevolutionary prospects of any lineage. The solution
    lies in recognizing that spandrels, although architecturally consequential, are not
    doomed to a secondary or unimportant status thereby. Spandrels, and all other
    forms of exaptive potential, define the ground of evolvability, and play as
    important a role in macro-evolutionary potential as conventional adaptation does
    for the immediacy of microevolutionary success. I emphasize the centrality of the
    exaptive pool for solving the problem of evolvability by presenting a full
    taxonomy of categories for the pool's richness, focusing on a primary distinction
    between "franklins" (or inherent potentials of structures evolved for other adaptive
    roles— that is, the classical Darwinian functional shifts that do not depart from
    adaptationism), and "miltons" (or true nonadaptations, arising from several
    sources, with spandrels as a primary category, and then available for later
    cooptation from the exaptive pool—that is, the class of nonadaptive origins that
    does challenge the dominant role of panadaptationism in evolutionary theory).

  3. I argue that the concept of cross-level spandrels vastly increases the
    range, power and importance of nonadaptation in evolution, and also unites the two
    central themes of this book by showing how the hierarchically expanded theory of
    selection also implies a greatly increased scope for non-adaptive structural
    constraint as an important factor in the potentiation of macroevolution.


Chapter 12: Tiers of time and trials of extrapolationism


  1. Darwin clearly recognized the threat of catastrophic mass extinction to the
    extrapolationist and uniformitarian premises underlying his claim for full

Free download pdf