Philosophy in Dialogue : Plato's Many Devices

(Barré) #1
IS THERE METHOD IN THIS MADNESS?


  1. For the recognition that the wreath of ivy and violets represents both
    Dionysus and Athens, see Rojcewicz, “Platonic Love,” 111.

  2. Scott recognizes the grounding function of Alcibiades’ speech when he
    writes: “It makes concrete and particular the Eros that had become quite ab-
    stract in Diotima’s speech, and it returns the conversation to the everyday world
    of human concerns.” See Scott, Plato’s Socrates as Educator, 120 – 21.

  3. Rosen contends: “The phrase ‘from left to right’ suggests that Aris-
    tophanes is now between Agathon and Socrates.” See Rosen, Plato’s Sympo-
    sium, 325.

  4. The deep and complex relationship between the Republic and Sym-
    posium has been recognized by Strauss. See Strauss, On Plato’s Symposium, 19.
    His student, Stanley Rosen, further determines the nature of this relationship
    along the lines outlined here. See Stanley Rosen, “The Role of Eros in Plato’s
    Republic,” Review of Metaphysics 18 (1965): 452–75.

  5. Because the dramatic date of the Republic is ambiguous, it remains un-
    clear whether the “Glaucon” referred to in the Symposium is Plato’s brother who
    appears in the Republic. Friedländer recognizes that the name “Glaucon,” even
    if it is not Plato’s brother, calls the Republic to mind. He claims: “The scene at
    the beginning of the Republic is reminiscent of the Symposium in its very words.”
    See Paul Friedländer, Plato: The Dialogues, Second and Third Periods, vol. 3 (Prince-
    ton: Princeton University Press, 1969), 6.

  6. There is a long history of interpretations that fail to recognize the func-
    tion of the playfulness of the Republic. One of the best expressions of this tradi-
    tion is found in Popper’s Open Society and Its Enemies, which sees the philosopher
    king of the Republic as “Plato himself, and the Republic is Plato’s own claim for
    kingly power.” Popper goes on to assert that the Republic is “meant by its author
    not so much as a theoretical treatise, but as topical political manifesto.” See
    Karl Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. 1 (Princeton: Princeton Uni-
    versity Press, 1943), 153. The presumption that the Republic is a political treatise
    in the modern sense, or, more radically, a manifesto, are anachronisms that fail
    to recognize the ambiguities Plato wrote into the text itself.

  7. These words: “ΔAllΔ eij dokei,... ou{tw crh; poiein” are parroted in the
    Symposium by Apollodorus’: “eij ou\n deikai; uJmi'n dihghvsasqai, tau'ta crh; poiein”
    (173c).

  8. Plato, Republic of Plato, 441.

  9. John Sallis recognizes that Socrates establishes a community by turn-
    ing force into persuasion. See John Sallis, Being and Logos: Reading the Platonic
    Dialogues, 3rd ed. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1996), 322.

  10. Recognizing the importance of coercion at the start of book 5, Jacob
    Howland suggests that Adeimantus and Polemarchus envision themselves as
    the noble guardians who will receive the full pleasure of erotic procreation
    in the city Socrates establishes in speech. See Jacob Howland, “The Republic’s
    Third Wave and the Paradox of Political Philosophy,” Review of Metaphysics 51,
    no. 3 (1998): 646.

  11. Philebus 48a– e.

Free download pdf