Species and the Birth of Modern Science 99
... but not content with this, they are unable to banish the thought that behind these
varieties there is but one genus, nay, that there might even be a common principle for
the earth and the salts.^230
Parsimony is due to the need for the understanding to reduce multiplicities into
unities. This is exactly what the scholastics would have sought. But he then continues:
The logical principle of genera, which postulates identity, is balanced by another prin-
ciple, namely that of species, which calls for manifoldness and diversity in things, not-
withstanding their agreement as coming under the same genus, and which prescribes
to the understanding that it attend to the diversity no less than to the identity.^231
Observation of things must discriminate, he says, as much as the “faculty of wit”
must nd the appropriate universal. This differs from the scholastic account, and in
some ways is more like Cusa’s contraction in species. Here, observation allows us to
group diversity of species under general predicates, he says, for if
... there were no lower concepts, there could not be higher concepts. Now the under-
standing can have knowledge only through concepts, and therefore, however far it car-
ries the process of division, never through mere intuition, but always again through
lower concepts. The knowledge of appearances in their complete determination, which
is possible only through the understanding, demands an endless progress in the speci-
cation of our concepts, and an advance to yet other remaining differences, from which
we have made an abstraction in the concept of the species, and still more so in that of
the genus.^232
Kant has it both ways after all: we abstract our more general categories from
empirical observation, and understanding divides categories logically so that reason
can deal with them.^233 But species border each other; there is a logical continuum
admitting of no transition from one to another per saltum, but only through all the
smaller degrees of difference between them.^234
This he calls the logical law of the continuum specierum, a version of the tran-
scendental law of lex continui in natura, which is Leibniz’s law of continuity. While
this applies to the realm of possible concepts, though, Kant rejects it in nature:
For in the rst place, the species in nature are actually divided, and must therefore con-
stitute a quantum discretum. ... And further, in the second place, we could not make
any determinate empirical use of this law, since it instructs us only in quite general
terms that we are to seek for grades of afnity, and yields no criterion whatsoever as to
how far, and in what manner, we are to prosecute the search for them.^235
(^230) Op. cit. B680f.
(^231) Op. cit. B682.
(^232) Op. cit. B684.
(^233) Op. cit. B695f.
(^234) Op. cit. B687.
(^235) Op. cit. B689.