Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon tWo: tHe BRAIn


Pain - has an Element of Blank -
It cannot recollect
When it begun - Or if there were
A time when it was not -
(Emily Dickinson, The Poems of Emily Dickinson, 1999 [1890], pp. 339–340)
But what if you have no arm? Amputees who experience phantom limbs some-
times suffer excruciating pain in a knee, elbow, or finger that doesn’t physically
exist. Their pain feels as clearly physically located as yours does.

We began with ‘pain hurts’, but perhaps we should say ‘pain hurts me’. What makes
pain painful is the fact that I don’t like it; that it’s my pain and I wish I didn’t have it.
Can there then be pains without selves who feel them? And if a self is needed, just
how much of a self, and what could the NCs of those necessary selves be?
Consider the case of a dog whose spinal cord has
been severed. If a painful stimulus is applied to its leg,
the dog shows no signs of distress, but its leg auto-
matically withdraws. Occasionally the same thing
happens in humans if they have broken their neck
or spine. If prodded in the leg they will deny feeling
anything, although their leg pulls back. The isolated
spinal cord can even be taught to make responses
by training it with stimuli that would be painful for a
person with no such injury, but which are not felt at all
by the paralysed person.
So, does the spinal cord feel the pain? This is not a
daft question. The idea of conscious spinal cords may
seem silly, but if you reject this idea then you must
also reject the idea that simple animals who have
only the equivalent of spinal cords (and no human-
like brain) can feel pain. There are also problems
with the role of pain in learning. Is the actual feeling
of pain, or a pain quale, a necessary component of
avoidance learning? If you say ‘no’, you are led to
epiphenomenalism and the possibility of pain-free
zombies who learn without experiencing the pain. If
you say ‘yes’, then in a simple or damaged organism
surely the isolated spinal cord does feel pain, even
if it is not like pain in a much more complex whole
organism.
Euan Macphail (1998) is among those who deny
that other animals can feel pleasure and pain, even
though they can learn. Antonio Damasio argues that
a self is needed for feeling pain. He argues that neu-
ral patterns are not enough – for pain to be painful,
and to have the emotional qualities it does, you also
have to know that you are feeling it.

PHAntom PHenomenA
After losing an arm or leg, more than 90%
of people experience a vivid ‘phantom limb’
that can last for years or even decades.
there are also reports of phantom breasts,
phantom jaws, and even phantom penises
that have phantom erections. Phantom legs
can be cramped into uncomfortable positions
and hands clenched so hard that the fingers
seem to be cutting into the hand. the pain
can be excruciating and terribly hard to
treat (melzack, 1992; Ramachandran and
Blakeslee, 1998).
the thought of pain in a non-existent limb
is so odd that when silas Weir mitchell
coined the term ‘phantom limb’ in 1871,
after thousands who fought in the Ameri-
can Civil War had had limbs removed from
injury or gangrene, he wrote anonymously
for fear of ridicule. But it was later studied
by merleau-Ponty as a way of delving into the problems
of mind–body-dualism. so where is the pain, and what
causes it? An obvious theory is that damaged nerves in the
stump send signals to the brain which, wrongly, assumes

C


on


C


e


P


t


4.2


Knowing that you have pain requires something
else that occurs after the neural patterns that
correspond to the substrate of pain – the
nociceptive signals – are displayed in the
appropriate areas of the brain stem, thalamus,
and cerebral cortex and generate an image of
pain, a feeling of pain.
(Damasio, 1999, p. 73)

This next stage is also in the brain. It is ‘the neu-
ral pattern of you knowing, which is just another
name for consciousness’ (p. 73). This means that
the necessary neural correlates for pain are to
have both the activity in the pain system, and the
neural pattern of self – and both are not just cor-
relates, but causes.
Saying that feeling pain depends on knowing
you are in pain allows Damasio to distinguish
between self-willed actions and automatic
reactions, such as removing your hand from
the hotplate before you even felt the pain  – in
this case, there is no pain before the action,
only afterwards once your knowledge catches
up. But Damasio undermines his own argument
by saying that even the first pattern alone
‘generate[s] an image of pain, a feeling of pain’
(Damasio, 1999, p. 73). He claims that the feel-
ing of pain depends on knowing one is in pain,
but at the same time he still relies on the more
traditional assumption that nociceptive signals
alone can be sufficient. Notice also that the neu-
ral patterns are ‘displayed’, and that the ‘feeling

‘the neural pattern of


you knowing, which is


just another name for


consciousness’


(Damasio, 1999, p. 73)

Free download pdf