Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon tWo: tHe BRAIn
    senses in sensory substitution (Chapter 8)? On the ‘moder-
    ate sensory pluralism’ account (Fulkerson, 2014), individ-
    ual senses and the multimodal interactions between them
    have to be differently categorised depending on the con-
    text, so puzzling over the integration of discrete modalities
    may be creating a problem where there isn’t one.
    Some combination of sensory distinctness and multisensory
    integration makes possible a world in which objects can be
    recognised as whole, and as being touched, seen, tasted,
    smelled, or heard, and as being the same thing however we
    perceive them. Many brain areas are known to be involved,
    including primary sensory cortices, frontal lobe, the supe-
    rior colliculus in the midbrain, and many subcortical areas,
    but just how this kind of integration gives rise to the sub-
    jective sense of being one self in a unified world remains to
    be seen.


INTEGRATED INFORMATION


THEORY


The unity of consciousness is the starting point for the inte-
grated information theory (IIT) of consciousness (Tononi,
2004, 2007, 2008, 2015), discussed briefly in Chapter  5. This
developed out of Edelman and Tononi’s (2000a, 2000b)
dynamic core hypothesis, in which re-entrant thalamocortical
loops produce high levels of dynamic complexity that create
consciousness. According to IIT, consciousness corresponds
to the capacity of a system to integrate information. Infor-
mation is integrated if it cannot be localised in any individual
part of the system, or is ‘generated by causal interactions in
the whole, over and above the information generated by the
parts’ (Tononi, 2008, p. 221).
IIT sets out to explain five key features of consciousness.
1 Intrinsic existence. My conscious experience exists here and now, from my
intrinsic perspective.
2 Composition. Consciousness is structured: it is composed of multiple phe-
nomenal distinctions at different levels of generality, like a red colour, a traffic
light, the left side, a red traffic light on the left, etc.
3 Information. Every conscious experience is specific and differentiated from
other possible experiences; its distinctions specify spatial locations, as well
as positive concepts  – like road as opposed to no road, red as opposed to
amber or green, etc. – and negative concepts – no red, no country lane, no
beach, etc.
4 Exclusion. Each experience is definite in both content and spatio-temporal
‘grain’, making some phenomenal distinctions  – driving along a road and
coming to a red light – and not others, and flowing at one speed not another.
5 Integration. Seeing the red traffic light cannot be reduced to seeing the
colour red plus a traffic light.

PRoFILe 6.1
Giulio Tononi
Giulio Tononi is a neuroscientist
and psychiatrist based at the
University of Wisconsin, where
he holds chairs in sleep medi-
cine as well as in consciousness
science. After studying medicine
at the University of Pisa in Italy,
he specialised in psychiatry and
served as a medical officer in

the army before doing a doctorate in neuroscience. Long


fascinated by sleep and the reasons we need so much of


it, he has worked on human, mouse, and fruit-fly models;


explored genetics, proteins, and computer analysis; and,


with Chiara Cirelli, developed the ‘synaptic homeostasis’


hypothesis that sleep serves to regulate the excessive


synaptic activation of wakefulness. Together with Gerald


Edelman, he developed the dynamic core hypothesis, a


model of consciousness which he expanded into integrat-


ed information theory and has continued to update. In


IIT, a system’s consciousness is determined by its caus-


al properties and corresponds to a system’s capacity to


integrate information, an idea which is supported by


the breakdown of information integration in slow-wave


sleep, general anaesthesia, and vegetative states.

Free download pdf