Consciousness

(Tuis.) #1

  • seCtIon FoUR: eVoLUtIon
    This, Humphrey argues, is how sensations came about. The
    response circuits were then privatised and internalised, and per-
    ceptions developed in a separate stream, but sensations still bear
    the hallmark of their origins in bodily expression. This changes
    the problem of consciousness by putting sensation on the side of
    agency rather than reception, and this is how Humphrey (2000)
    wants to solve the mind–body problem. Whether or not you
    agree that turning sensations into actions really does solve the
    mind–body problem, such enactive or sensorimotor theories do
    not need to ask how or why consciousness evolved in its own right
    because consciousness is not something separate from action.
    This is also true of predictive-processing theories of conscious-
    ness (e.g. Seth et al., 2012), which treat consciousness as the
    result of top-down predictions generated throughout the course of our brain–
    body–world interactions. These probability-based predictions are shaped by
    prior knowledge accumulated over the lifespan. They take the form of interocep-
    tive signals that, when they successfully match sensory inputs, yield conscious
    experience. In these respects, predictive processing can be seen as extending and
    adapting Humphrey’s ideas by introducing the concept of Bayesian probability in
    a widely distributed system.
    Humphrey goes on to explain why consciousness seems to matter to us so much:
    ‘it is its function to matter’ and to seem mysterious and other-worldly (2006, p.
    131). Ancestors who believed in a mysterious consciousness and an unworldly
    self would have taken themselves more seriously and placed more value on their
    own and others’ lives. This is why belief in mind–body duality evolved.
    So, on his ‘reductionist theory of what phenomenal consciousness is – it is a magic
    show that you stage for yourself inside your own head’ (2011, pp. 198–199). This
    sounds very much as though Humphrey is calling consciousness an illusion. He
    likens our ‘magical mystery show’ to such visual illusions as the impossible tri-
    angle or the Penrose stairs made famous by M.C. Escher’s paintings of impossi-
    ble stairways, calling it an ‘ipsundrum’: an ‘illusion generating inner creation in
    response to sensory stimulation’.


Yet, in the end, Humphrey (2016) denies illusionism, and his denial keeps his the-
ory firmly in this section. If ‘sensations are representations of something we do’
(2016, p. 117), internalising responses to incoming stimulation and making sense
of them, then sensations have real effects in the world. Natural selection would
operate on these effects and eventually lead to the kinds of minds we have today.
Consciousness may be a magic show, but its effects are real enough.

THE EVOLUTION OF ILLUSION


Others disagree. Our last possibility is that phenomenal consciousness, as usu-
ally conceived, is illusory (Chapter 3). Illusions themselves may have effects, but
experiences do not have phenomenal or ‘what-it’s-like-to-be’ properties, and ‘con-
sciousness itself ’ does not exist. So natural selection has nothing to work on. Just
as Frankish (2016b) has argued for replacing the hard problem with the illusion
problem, so we should be replacing the question ‘how did consciousness evolve?’
with ‘how did the illusion of consciousness evolve?’

‘it is our capacity to tell


others of the contents of


our consciousness that


confers the evolutionary


advantage’


(Halligan and Oakley, 2015,
p. 27)


‘[Consciousness] is a


magic show that you


stage for yourself inside


your own head’


(Humphrey, 2011, p. 199)


‘illusionism [. . .] should


be considered the front


runner’


(Dennett, 2016, p. 65)


FIGURE 11.9 • Humphrey (2011) likens
consciousness to visual illusions
such as these Penrose stairs.

Free download pdf