Interpretation and Method Empirical Research Methods and the Interpretive Turn

(Ann) #1

88 MEANING AND METHODOLOGY



  1. I am indebted to the discussion in Monk (2004, esp. 39–42) for helping me articulate this connection.

  2. As noted above, this positioned moral and value statements, for example, beyond the realm of science
    because they were seen as products of emotion, rather than reason.

  3. His example of bicycle riding illustrates this: If you know how to ride a bicycle, you know which way
    to turn the front wheel when falling to the right; otherwise, you would always be falling and could not claim
    to hold that knowledge. But most bicycle riders asked this question cannot articulate their knowledge. Fur-
    thermore, even if they could, they could not write a manual naming all the rules for riding a bicycle. More-
    over, even if they could write such a manual, no novice could read it, get on a bicycle, and ride off without
    falling—absent learning the “tacit knowledge” (in this case, of a kinesthetic sort) that experienced riders
    know but cannot articulate.

  4. I take as evidence of this several sections of the 2004 report on “Scientific Foundations of Qualitative
    Research” (Ragin, Nagel, and White 2004).

  5. In fact, Lakoff and Johnson’s claim that objectivity concerns self-control (1999, 277) sheds another
    light on this argument concerning the uses of “objectivity” to control researchers’ behaviors—namely, that
    its rhetorical usage for control purposes stems from a fear of bodies being “out of control.” I do not have the
    space here to develop this implication of these two arguments.

  6. The fact that many political science doctoral students and junior faculty fear to self-identify when
    posting to the Perestroika list—indeed, the existence of that group at all, as an outlet for constructive criti-
    cism of the American Political Science Association—attests to the power of these controls.

Free download pdf