MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
208 Aristotle and his school

and to take into account the overarching framework of ‘principal activities

and affections’K D

   #Lof living beings for the sake of which,


according to Aristotle, these parts and processes exist or occur.^8

The result might well be a morecompletepicture of Aristotle’s views

on what it means to be a living being, that is to say, on how the various

constituents that make up a living entity are interrelated. For, as Aristotle

himself indicates, a purely formal description of psychic powers and pro-

cesses is insufficient for at least two reasons. First, as he repeatedly stresses

(apparently in polemics against the Pythagoreans), the connection of a cer-

tain psychic function with a certain bodily structure (an organ such as the

eye, a process such as heating) is by no means coincidental; on the contrary,

the bodily basis should have a certain nature or be in a certain condition in

order to enable the exercise of a certain psychic power (e.g. perception).^9

Secondly, the material, bodily embedding of psychic functions accounts

for the occurrence ofvariationsK

Lboth in the distribution of


these functions over various kinds of animals and in their exercise. These

variations may exist, or occur, among different species, but also among in-

dividual members of one species, or amongtypesof individuals within one

species, or even within one individual organism at different moments or

states (e.g. sleep versus waking, drunkenness versus sobriety). As this chap-

ter will try to show, variations inintellectualcapacities and performances

among different kinds of animals, among different members of one kind or

even within one individual on different occasions are explained by Aristotle

with a reference tobodilyfactors.^10 This raises the interesting question of

the causal relationship between these intellectual performances and the

bodily conditions corresponding to them, both in abnormal cases and in

normal ones, and how the form–matter distinction is to be applied in these

various circumstances: does form fail to ‘master’ matter in these cases, and

if so, why? Should we speak ofoneform (e.g. rationality) being present in

different pieces of matter, or should we say that there are different levels

on which the form–matter distinction can be made (as in typological vari-

ations)? Are the variations to be explained mechanically or teleologically,

and are defects compensated for by other skills?

In spite of this pronouncedly biological context, however, thereareindi-

cations that the study of the soul has, for Aristotle, a special status and is

(^8) SeePart. an. 645 b 15 – 28. This approach is illustrated by Lloyd ( 1992 ).
(^9) SeeDe an. 412 a 15 , 21 ; 412 b 5 , 12 ; 414 a 22 , 26.
(^10) This is not to say that other factors, such as habit and education (
 !0 
) play no role
here; on the extent to which, according to Aristotle, cultural factors (education, local customs) may
account for variations in the degree of perfection of these capacities, see below.

Free download pdf