MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
230 Aristotle and his school

($0 


0  ).^78 Whether they always are, or only in abnormal


cases, or whether the influence in abnormal cases is of a different kind rather

than of a different degree compared with normal cases is hard to decide, for

these bodily conditions are mostly referred to by Aristotle in the context of a

discussion ofvariationsin intellectual performances (type ( 3 ) distinguished

above, p. 217 ). It is clear, however, that apart from incidental bodily states

such as drunkenness or sleep (which may be characterised as disturbing

agents, although the former is1 -

, the latter1 -
), there


are also more structural conditions such as the quality of the blood, age,

the overall balance between warm and cold in the body and the quality of

the skin. Variations in these structural conditions account for variations in

intellectual capacities. The variations exist among different species, but also

among individual members of one species or types within a species, such as

dwarfs or melancholics. For the most part, these types represent ‘imperfect’

("  ) or ‘deformed’ ( #) 

) groups of human beings with spe-


cial characteristics due to their physical aberrations. However, some types

(such as the !

) seem to represent special classes of humans


whose distinctive characteristics are not to be regarded as deformations, but

as variationswithinone species that may be either conducive, or harmful,

or just neutral to the exercise of certain psychic powers.

We hear very little about what the bodily conditions of a normal, success-

ful operation of the intellectual powers are, but, as I have already said, there

is good reason to assume that this is just because, in the writings that have

survived, Aristotle simply does not have much reason to dwell on them.

Our picture of Aristotle’s psycho-physiology is likely to remain very incom-

plete – as is also indicated by the difficulties involved in piecing together his

scattered remarks about physiological conditions such aspneuma, blood,

and so forth. This has perhaps to do with his indebtedness to a medical

tradition which supplied a lot of material which he could simply take for

granted. As has already been demonstrated by Tracy – and is confirmed by

more recent work on Aristotle’s acquaintance with medical literature^79 –

this indebtedness is probably much greater than the scanty references to

medical authorities in Aristotle’s works suggest. In this particular context,

the Hippocratic workOn Regimencomes to one’s mind, which in chapters

35 and 36 has an extremely interesting discussion on variations in intellectual

performance due to variations in the proportion between fire and water in

(^78) Other, more peripheral evidence (dealing less explicitly withintellectualcapacities) is discussed in
ch. 5 above. See also Tracy ( 1969 ),passim.
(^79) For further references to scholarly discussions of Aristotle’s relation to medical literature see ch. 9 ;
see also Longrigg ( 1995 ) and Oser-Grote ( 1997 ).

Free download pdf