MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
20 Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity

add, like all other phenomena), has its own ‘nature’, its peculiar determined,

normal, stable and self-contained identity. Knowledge of this identity, and

of the regularity that results from this, will allow one to recognise and

understand individual instances of the phenomenon, to predict its future

occurrence and by medical intervention influence it or even prevent it from

happening or spreading. And in making this claim, the author polemicises

against people whom he calls ‘magicians, quacks, charlatans’, who regard

the disease as a form of whimsical, unpredictable divine intervention or

even demonic possession and whose therapeutic practice is determined by

magical beliefs and procedures. He describes the development of the disease

from its earliest, prenatal and indeed ancestral stages; he identifies the brain

as the seat of consciousness (a theme I shall examine in greater depth in

chapter 4 ) and as the primary organ affected by the disease; he discusses a

whole range of additional factors, both internal and external, that set the

disease in motion or influence its actual development; and he gives a vivid

account of the various stages of an epileptic seizure, relating each of the

symptoms to a particular underlying physiological cause.

Yet for all the emphasis on the naturalness and ‘rationality’ of his ap-

proach, we shall see in chapter 1 that the author rules out neither the

divinity of the diseases nor the possibility of divine intervention as such.

He is distinguishing between an appropriate appeal to the gods for purifi-

cation from the ‘pollution’ (miasma) of moral transgressions (hamart ̄emata)

that has disturbed the relationship between man and the gods, and an in-

appropriate appeal to the gods for the purification of the alleged pollution

of the ‘so-called sacred disease’. This is inappropriate, he says, for diseases

are not sent by a god – to say so would be blasphemous, he insists – they

are natural phenomena which can be cured by natural means, and they do

not constitute a pollution in the religious sense. The text has often been

read as if the author ruled out divine ‘intervention’as such. But in fact,

there is no evidence that he does – indeed, he does not even rule out that

gods may cure diseases, if approached in the proper way and on the basis

of appropriate premises.

Such negative readings of the text attributing to the author the ruling

out of all forms of divine intervention have presumably been inspired by

a wishful belief among interpreters to ‘rationalise’ or ‘secularise’ Hippo-

cratic medicine – a belief possibly inspired by the desire to see Hippocratic

medicine as the forerunner of modern biomedicine, and which can be par-

alleled with interpretative tendencies to ‘demythologise’ philosophers such

as Parmenides, Pythagoras and Empedocles to make them fit our concept

of ‘philosophy’ more comfortably. Yet recently, there has been a renewed

appreciation of the ‘mythical’ or ‘religious’ aspects of early Greek thought,
Free download pdf